It takes
a strong philosopher to assume control of a preposition and propel it into a
foreign language. That is what Friedrich Nietzsche did with the word über. In
German, it can mean “over,” “beyond,” or “about.” You are reading an essay über
Nietzsche. As a prefix, über is sometimes equivalent to the English
“super”—übernatürlich is “supernatural”—but it has less of an aggrandizing
effect. Nietzsche altered the destiny of the word when, in the
eighteen-eighties, he began speaking of the Übermensch, which has been
translated as “superman,” “superhuman,” and “overman.” Scholars still debate
what Nietzsche had in mind. A physically stronger being? A spiritual
aristocrat? A kind of cyborg? “Overperson” might be the most literal equivalent
in English, although it is unlikely that DC Comics would have sold many comic
books using that title.
In 1903,
three years after Nietzsche’s death, George Bernard Shaw published his play
“Man and Superman,” in which he equated the Übermensch with an overflowing
“Life Force.” Three decades later, Jerry Siegel and Joe Shuster, two Cleveland
teen-agers, created the first “Super-Man” story, depicting the character not as
a caped hero but as a bald, telepathic villain bent on “total annihilation.”
Super-Man soon reëmerged as a muscle-bound defender of the good, and during the
Second World War he jumped into the fight against the Nazis. It’s unclear
whether Siegel and Shuster knew of Nietzsche in 1933, but the word “superman”
hardly existed in English before the philosopher’s ideas began to spread.
As
Nietzsche worked his wiles on generations of English-speaking college students,
the word Übermensch increasingly stood on its own, and “über” slipped into
English as a prefix. In the nineteen-eighties, Spy described the Hollywood
agent Michael Ovitz as an “über-agent.” The umlaut-free car-sharing service
Uber, originally known as UberCab, is a related development, hinting at Silicon
Valley fantasies of world domination. In the late twentieth century, the word
“super” rebounded into German as all-purpose slang for “very”; if you wish to
describe something as really, really cool, you say that it is super super toll.
Somewhere, Nietzsche is laughing hysterically while screaming in anguish.
The
adventures of “super” and “über” are a case study in the inescapability of
Nietzsche’s philosophy, which has affected everyday discourse and modern
political reality like no body of thought before it. Countless books on
Nietzsche are published in dozens of languages each year, linking him to every
imaginable zone of life and culture. One can read about the French Nietzsche,
the American Nietzsche, the pragmatic Nietzsche, the analytic Nietzsche, the
feminist Nietzsche, the gay Nietzsche, the black Nietzsche, the
environmentalist Nietzsche. Lurking amid the crowd of avatars is the
proto-fascist Nietzsche—the proponent of pitilessness, hardness, and the will
to power who is cited approvingly by such far-right gurus as Alain de Benoist,
Richard Spencer, and Aleksandr Dugin. Can a philosopher who has sown such
confusion be said to possess a coherent identity? Or, as Bertrand Russell once
argued, is Nietzsche merely a literary phenomenon?
When I
was in college, in the nineteen-eighties, the French Nietzsche held sway. It
was the heyday of post-structuralism, and Nietzsche appeared to anticipate one
of the central insights of that era: that we are at the mercy of ever-shifting
systems and perspectives. The work of Michel Foucault, Gilles Deleuze, and
Jacques Derrida is all but inconceivable without Nietzsche’s example. So many
professors distributed photocopies of the 1873 essay “On Truth and Lie in an
Extra-Moral Sense” that we could have recited it as a postmodern pledge of
allegiance: “What, then, is truth? A mobile army of metaphors, metonyms, and
anthropomorphisms. . . . Truths are illusions about which one has forgotten
that this is what they are.”
In the
past few decades, other Nietzsches have come to the fore. Anglo-American
philosophers have aligned him with various schools of post-analytic thought, seeing
him as an idiosyncratic kind of psychologist or sociologist. Nietzsche’s
political thinking is also a trending topic, although his ideas are devilishly
difficult to reconcile with modern conceptions of left and right. He raged
against democracy and egalitarianism, but also against nationalism and
anti-Semitism. Nietzsche is often quoted in the chat rooms of the far right,
and he also surfaces regularly in leftist discussions about the future of
democracy.
Walter
Kaufmann, the German-American émigré whose translations of Nietzsche were long
the standard versions in English, once declared that the philosopher’s writings
are “easier to read but harder to understand than those of almost any other
thinker.” Ideologues keep trying to appropriate him because they want his
rhetorical firepower on their side. Yet Nietzsche, like his fallen idol Richard
Wagner, is at once emphatic and ambiguous, overbearing and elusive. Nietzsche’s
famous adage that there are “no facts, only interpretations” is among his more
debatable propositions, but it applies perfectly well to his own infuriating,
invigorating body of work.
The
itinerant, solitary, sickly life of Nietzsche has been told many times, most
recently in English by the biographer Sue Prideaux, in “I Am Dynamite!” The
title comes from an unnerving passage in “Ecce Homo,” Nietzsche’s
autobiographical book of 1888, which was completed a couple of months before he
descended into insanity, at the age of forty-four:
I know my lot. One day my name will be
linked to the memory of something monstrous [etwas Ungeheueres]—to a crisis
like none there has been on earth, to the most profound collision of
conscience, to a verdict invoked against everything that until then had been
believed, demanded, held sacred. I am no man, I am dynamite.
How a
Lutheran pastor’s son, trained in classical philology, ended up on that
precipice of brilliance and madness is the essential drama of Nietzsche’s life.
The passage has been read as an eerie premonition of his future appropriation
by the Nazis—although there is no way of knowing exactly what kind of crisis is
meant. Ungeheuer is an ambiguous word, hovering between the monstrous and the
gigantic. Kaufmann translated it as “tremendous,” which takes away too much of
the ominousness. Here is the sumptuous difficulty of Nietzsche: when you drill
down on a word, an abyss of interpretation opens.
Nietzsche
grew up in the village of Röcken, outside Leipzig. The church where his father
preached still stands; Nietzsche, the scourge of Christianity, is buried in a
plot next to the building. The elder Nietzsche, like his son, was afflicted by
severe physical and mental problems—violent headaches, epileptic strokes,
amnesiac episodes—and died at the age of thirty-five, when Friedrich was four.
Nietzsche himself had a mental breakdown in middle age. The old story that his
breakdown stemmed from syphilis is now widely doubted; a likelier explanation
is a hereditary neurological or vascular disorder. Neurologists in Belgium and
Switzerland have concluded that he had cadasil, a genetic condition that causes
repeated strokes.
“I Am
Dynamite!” lacks the philosophical scope of prior biographies by Rüdiger
Safranski and Julian Young, but Prideaux is a stylish and witty narrator. She
begins with the pivotal event in Nietzsche’s life: his introduction, in 1868,
to Wagner, the most consequential German cultural figure of the day. Nietzsche
would soon assume a professorship in Basel, at the astonishingly young age of
twenty-four, but he jumped at the chance to join the Wagner operation. For the
next eight years, as Wagner completed his operatic cycle “The Ring of the
Nibelung” and prepared for its première, Nietzsche served as a propagandist for
the Wagnerian cause and as the Meister’s factotum. He then broke away,
declaring his intellectual independence first with coded critiques and then
with unabashed polemics. Accounts of this immensely complicated relationship
are too often distorted by prejudice on one side or another. Nietzscheans and
Wagnerians both tend to off-load ideological problems onto the rival camp;
Prideaux succumbs to this temptation. She insists that Nietzsche’s talk of a
superior brood of “blond beasts” has no modern racial connotation, and casts
Wagner’s Siegfried as an Aryan hero who “rides to the redemption of the world.”
In fact, Siegfried is a fallen hero who rides nowhere; the redeemer of the
world is Brünnhilde.
Prideaux’s
picture of the Wagner-Nietzsche relationship fails to explain either the
intensity of their bond or the trauma of their break. Early on, Nietzsche was
hopelessly infatuated with Wagner’s music and personality. He described the
friendship as “my only love affair.” As with many infatuations, Nietzsche’s
expectations were wildly exaggerated. He hoped that the “Ring” would revive the
cultural paradise of ancient Greece, fusing Apollonian beauty and Dionysian
savagery. He envisaged an audience of élite aesthetes who would carry a
transfiguring message to the outer world. Wagner, too, revered Greek culture,
but he was fundamentally a man of the theatre, and tailored his ideals to the
realities of the stage. At the first Bayreuth Festival, in 1876, Nietzsche was
crestfallen to discover that a viable theatre operation required the patronage
of the nouveau riche and the fashionable.
Personal
differences between the two men provide amusing anecdotes. Nietzsche made
sporadic attempts at musical composition, one of which caused Wagner to have a
laughing fit. (The music is not very good, but it is not as bad as all that.)
Wagner also suggested to Nietzsche’s doctor that the young man’s medical issues
were the result of excessive masturbation. But the disagreements went much
deeper, revealing a rift between ideologies and epochs. Wagner embodied the
nineteenth century, in all its grandeur and delusion; Nietzsche was the
dynamic, destructive torchbearer of the twentieth.
When
they first met, they shared an admiration for the philosophical pessimism of
Arthur Schopenhauer, who saw a world governed by the insatiable striving of the
will. Only through the renunciation of worldly desire, Schopenhauer posited,
can we free ourselves from our incessant drives. Aesthetic experience is one
avenue to self-overcoming—an idea that the art-besotted Nietzsche seized upon.
But he disdained Schopenhauer’s emphasis on the practice of compassion, which
also promises release from the grasping ego. Wagner, by contrast, claimed to
value compassion above all other emotions. “Parsifal,” his final opera, has as
its motto “Durch Mitleid wissend, der reine Tor” (“The pure fool, knowing
through pity”). Nietzsche’s 1878 book, “Human, All Too Human,” his inaugural
assault on Wagner and Romantic metaphysics, hammers away at the word Mitleid,
considering it an instrument of weakness. In its place, Nietzsche praises hardness,
force, cruelty. “Culture simply cannot do without passions, vices, and acts of
malice,” he writes.
These
views made Wagner wince, as the diaries of Cosima Wagner, his wife, attest. In
an earlier essay entitled “The Greek State,” Nietzsche had declared that
“slavery belongs to the essence of a culture.” The intellectual historian
Martin Ruehl speculates that Wagner persuaded Nietzsche to omit the essay from
his first book, “The Birth of Tragedy Out of the Spirit of Music” (1872), which
culminates in a paean to Wagner. During the same period, though, Nietzsche was
castigating German tendencies toward nationalist chauvinism and
anti-Semitism—conspicuous elements in Wagner’s political blatherings. What
seems particularly unfortunate about the break is that each man had an acute
sense of the other’s blindnesses.
Nietzsche
not only rejected the sublime longings of nineteenth-century Romanticism; he
also jettisoned the teleology of historical progress that had governed European
thought since the Renaissance, and that had found its most formidable advocate
in Hegel. Instead, Nietzsche grounded himself in a version of naturalism—the
post-Darwinian conviction that humans are an animal species, led by no
transcendent purpose. This turn yields Nietzsche’s most controversial concepts:
the announcement of the death of God; the “eternal return,” which frames
existence in terms of endlessly repeating cycles; and the will to power, which
involves a ceaseless struggle for survival and mastery. It might be said that
Nietzsche, in backing away from Wagner, backed into his own mature thought—the
celebration of Dionysian energy, the “triumphal yes to life over and above all
death and change.”
Between
his final meeting with Wagner, in 1876, and his mental collapse of 1889, Nietzsche
lived the life of an intellectual ascetic. Health problems caused him to resign
his professorship in 1879; from then on, he adopted a nomadic life style,
summering in the Swiss Alps and wintering, variously, in Genoa, Rapallo,
Venice, Nice, and Turin. He wrote a dozen books, of increasingly idiosyncratic
character, poised between philosophy, aphoristic cultural criticism, polemic,
and autobiography. He worked out many of his ideas during vigorous Alpine
hikes—a practice fondly re-created by John Kaag in the recent book “Hiking with
Nietzsche.” The possibility of a romance with the psychologist Lou
Andreas-Salomé arose and then subsided; a serious relationship was probably
beyond his reach. The landscape of the mind consumed his attention. As
Safranski wrote, “For Nietzsche, thinking was an act of extreme emotional
intensity. He thought the way others feel.”
Translating
Nietzsche is a difficult task, but the swagger of his prose, with its pithy
strikes and sudden swerves, can be fairly readily approximated in English.
Kaufmann, in his translations, brought to bear a strong, pugnacious style. In
his introductions and footnotes, he distanced Nietzsche from fascist
bombast—naming the Übermensch the “Overman” was just one strategy—and recast
him as a kind of existentialist. But Kaufmann underplayed Nietzsche’s slippery
elegance, and his choice not to translate “Human, All Too Human” and its
successor, “Dawn” (1881), gave a skewed view of the thinker’s development. A
series of translations from Cambridge University Press covered the gaps. Now
Stanford University Press is halfway through a nineteen-volume edition of
Nietzsche’s complete writings and notebooks. The press has been threatened with
cuts in funding, but if the project is achieved English readers will have, for
the first time, access to the entirety of Nietzsche’s work.
Since
1967, the German publisher De Gruyter has been amassing a critical edition of
Nietzsche’s complete writings, which can be browsed on a dizzyingly
comprehensive Web site, nietzschesource.org. This monumental project has, to
the annoyance of some scholars, attracted increasing attention to Nietzsche’s
extensive notebooks. These show a less awe-inspiring side of the philosopher,
as he jots down items from his reading and delivers utterances esoteric,
mundane, and bizarre:
When
five people speak together, a sixth always has to die.
The
Chinese eat very many dishes in very small portions.
I could
become the European Buddha.
If you
aren’t a bird, be careful not to camp above an abyss.
Woman is
so little satisfied with herself that she would rather permit herself to be
beaten than—
The last
thought is left blessedly unfinished. Nietzsche’s misogyny is a brute fact that
no pageant of interpretation can disguise.
Yet the
notebooks contain some of Nietzsche’s most vital, pungent writing. Consider a
remarkable passage from 1885, which appears in the most recent Stanford volume,
“Unpublished Fragments (Spring 1885–Spring 1886),” in a translation by Adrian
Del Caro. It has long been known to readers as the final section of “The Will
to Power,” Nietzsche’s posthumous so-called magnum opus, assembled under the
direction of his reactionary sister, Elisabeth Förster-Nietzsche, and published
in 1901. To come across it in the Stanford edition, free of Förster-Nietzsche’s
tendentious and often deceptive editorial practices, is a bracing shock:
And do you also know what “the
world” is to me? Should I show it to you in my mirror? This world: a colossus
[Ungeheuer] of energy, without beginning, without end, a firm, unshakable
magnitude of energy that does not get bigger, does not get smaller, that does
not expend itself but only transforms itself, as a whole unchangeable in size,
an economy without expenditures and losses, but likewise without growth,
without income, encased by “nothingness” as by its border, nothing blurring,
wasted, nothing infinitely extended, but laid into a definite space as a
definite force, and not a space that would be “empty” anywhere, rather as force
everywhere, as play of forces and waves of forces . . . this my Dionysian world
of eternal self-creating, of eternal self-destroying, this mystery-world of the
doubly voluptuous, this my beyond good and evil, without goal, if a goal does
not lie in the happiness of the circle, without will, if a ring does not have
good will for itself—do you want a name for this world? A solution for all its
riddles? a light for you too, you hiddenmost, strongest, most intrepid, most
midnightly?—This world is the will to power—and nothing else! And you
yourselves are also this will to power—and nothing else!
The
central sentence actually goes on for almost twice as long, disrupting the
rat-a-tat rhythm that is typical of Nietzsche’s later writing. He generally
resisted the epic long-windedness of nineteenth-century German prose, but here
he makes an exception as he verbally acts out the condition of universal flux.
An additional wrinkle is that the diction begins to resemble the ecstatic love
duets of Wagner’s “Tristan und Isolde” (“Without naming / Without parting /
Newly knowing / Newly burning”). You could quibble with this or that choice in
Del Caro’s rendering—the statuesque word “colossus” seems a poor choice for
Ungeheuer—but the passage has the right racing, dancing energy.
No creature
in Nietzsche’s menagerie of concepts has caused as much trouble as the will to
power. At first glance, this entity strongly resembles Schopenhauer’s
all-devouring will. For Martin Heidegger, the will to power was the last gasp
of metaphysics—an attempt to capture the “basic character of all beings,” which
Heidegger wishes to supplant with his post-metaphysical idea of
being-in-the-world. Gilles Deleuze, the chief guru of the French Nietzsche,
wrote, “The will to power is not force but the differential element which
simultaneously determines the relations of forces (quantity) and the respective
qualities of related forces.” One needn’t know exactly what Deleuze means here
to accept the underlying proposition that Nietzsche understands power less as a
struggle for domination over others than as a struggle for power over oneself.
Rather than fleeing abjectly from the will, as in Schopenhauer, one should seek
to harness it, master it, ride it out.
When
Nietzsche revisits this material, in “Beyond Good and Evil” (1886), he pulls
back abruptly, placing the will to power in a hypothetical, almost ironic
frame. He begins, “Supposing nothing were ‘given’ as real besides our world of
desires and passions . . .” After a series of qualifications, he concludes, “Supposing
finally that we were to succeed in explaining our entire life of drives as the
taking shape and ramification of a basic form of the will—namely of the will to
power, as my proposition has it . . . then we would have earned the right to
unequivocally determine all effective force as: will to power.” Nietzsche, for
all his bravado, likes to hedge his bets, as Tom Stern points out in the
introduction to “The New Cambridge Companion to Nietzsche.” He writes that the
philosopher’s style is one of “rhetorical questions, ellipses, fables,
mini-dialogues, hints that much is left unsaid, and apparent praise for seeming
to be other than you are.”
This
cyclone of nuance goes missing when we reduce Nietzsche to maxims. Nor should
we try to extract a system that can be summarized on a chalkboard. Ultimately,
his writing is a mode of criticism, of übersubjective intellectual reportage,
grounded in extreme self-awareness. Freud is said to have commented that
Nietzsche “had a more penetrating knowledge of himself than any other man who
ever lived or was ever likely to live.”
Monsters
lurk in the Nietzschean deep. It cannot be a random mishap that so many
unpleasant people have taken pleasure in his work. None other than Jacques
Derrida discouraged talk of “falsifications” of Nietzsche, fascist or
otherwise. “One can’t falsify just anything,” Derrida wrote, with unaccustomed
bluntness. (One can, in fact, falsify anything, as a glance at the morning
paper shows, but the point holds.) However selective the Nazi appropriation of
Nietzsche may have been, it replicated elements of his thought. He did write
that equality is the “greatest of all lies,” and divided humanity into a
hierarchy of the weak and the strong. Hans Stark, the head of the admissions
detail at Auschwitz, had a sign over his desk reading “Mitleid ist Schwäche”
(“Compassion Is Weakness”). This could be read as a crude condensation of
Nietzsche’s diatribe against compassion in “The Antichrist.”
Ronald
Beiner, in a new book entitled “Dangerous Minds: Nietzsche, Heidegger, and the
Return of the Far Right,” claims that the resurgence of far-right political
movements around the world is evidence of Nietzsche’s nefarious influence. His
hostility to absolute truth, Beiner writes, has “left us vulnerable to harsh new
ideologies that appear to regard respect for truth as a snare.” To be sure, a
circuitous chain of connections is needed to get from “Thus Spake Zarathustra”
and “Beyond Good and Evil” to Donald Trump’s ravings about “fake news” or the
vicious fictions of Sandy Hook conspiracy theorists. Merely to announce a high
regard for truth is no guarantee that truth will be uttered. Indeed, some of
the most hideous acts in history have been committed by people who believe
themselves to be in sole possession of absolute truth. In the American context,
merchants of hatred hardly need to look to a nineteenth-century German
philologist for inspiration: they can draw on older and deeper wells at home.
Beiner
is right to urge latter-day interpreters to abandon talk of an apolitical
Nietzsche, but he is arguing largely with a previous generation of scholars.
There is no lack of contemporary publications that deal forthrightly with
Nietzsche’s political thinking: these include Hugo Drochon’s “Nietzsche’s Great
Politics,” Tamsin Shaw’s “Nietzsche’s Political Skepticism,” and Gary Shapiro’s
“Nietzsche’s Earth: Great Events, Great Politics.” Stern catalogues Nietzsche’s
most problematic traits in the “Cambridge Companion,” although he adds the
caveat that “we must have more categories available to us than ‘Nazi/not-Nazi,’
‘anti-Semite/anti-anti-Semite,’ ‘far-sighted/foolish’ or ‘to be
attacked/defended at all costs.’ ”
A
recurring theme in these studies is that Nietzsche could be a fiercely
prescient analyst of democratic politics, and that we can learn from his
observations without following him into antidemocratic invective. In an essay
in the “Cambridge Companion,” Christa Davis Acampora writes, “A popular view of
Nietzsche regards him as an advocate of bald expressions of power, but he is
better understood as someone who investigates—rather than celebrates—power.”
Who can deny that human beings are a fundamentally predatory species, and that
no political system or moral code has yet tamed our worst impulses?
Nineteenth-century thinkers in the tradition of Hegel anticipated the
attainment of a perfected state of humanity; instead, as Nietzsche foresaw, a
century of unprecedented horrors ensued. During the Cold War, the powers that
defeated fascism brought the world to the brink of a nuclear war that would
have made the Second World War seem like a minor episode in comparison. Today,
anthropogenic climate change is causing mass extinctions. To quote Zarathustra:
“The Earth has a skin, and this skin has diseases. One of these diseases is
called, for example, ‘humanity.’ ”
Nietzsche’s
central insight about the modern state—one that greatly influenced the
sociology of Max Weber and the political thinking of Carl Schmitt—is that it
faces a crisis of authority. When power is no longer divinely ordained, the
right to govern is contested. In “Human, All Too Human,” Nietzsche predicted
that, as the democratic state secularized itself, there would be a surge of
religious fanaticism resistant to centralized government. On the other side, he
anticipated a zealous adherence to the state on the part of nonbelievers.
Religious forces might seize control again, engendering new forms of
enlightened despotism—“perhaps less enlightened and more fearful than before.”
These struggles could go on for a while, Nietzsche writes. In one long
paragraph, he prophesies the history of the twentieth century, from fascism to
theocracy.
To the
opponents of democracy, Nietzsche says, in essence: Just wait. Liberal
democracy will devour itself, creating conditions for authoritarian rule.
Disorder and instability will sow distrust in politics itself. “Step by step,
private companies will absorb the functions of the state,” Nietzsche writes.
“Even the most tenacious remnants of the old work of governing (the activity,
for example, that is supposed to protect private persons from one another) will
finally be taken care of by private entrepreneurs.” The distinction between
public and private spheres will disappear. The state will give way to the
“liberation of the private person (I take care not to say: of the individual).”
And here
we are, in the twenty-first-century world of laissez-faire economics and
unregulated Big Tech monopolies. As the political philosopher Urs Marti has
pointed out, Nietzsche sometimes sounds less like a proto-Nazi than like a
neoliberal or a libertarian. A notebook entry from 1885-86 looks ahead to “a
superior kind of human being that thanks to its preponderance of willing,
knowing, wealth and influence, makes use of democratic Europe as its most
pliable and flexible tool for taking the destinies of the earth in hand, for
shaping ‘the human being’ itself as an artist would.” Silicon Valley tycoons
strive to become just such übermenschlich innovators. The entrepreneur Peter
Thiel, an avid reader of Nietzsche, says things like “I no longer believe that
freedom and democracy are compatible.” In this light, Nietzsche’s opposition to
nationalism and anti-Semitism looks less virtuous. For tech billionaires,
national and racial hatreds are inconveniences; their authoritarianism wears a
cosmopolitan face, promising frictionless commerce for all.
Is that
what Nietzsche wants? His avoidance of the word “individual,” in favor of
“private person,” suggests skepticism. And a crucial aspect of his world view
militates against monopolistic power. In 1995, Lawrence Hatab published a
fascinating book called “A Nietzschean Defense of Democracy,” which emphasizes
the philosopher’s attachment to the Greek agon—competition among worthy
adversaries, whether athletic or artistic. Hatab revisits that connection in an
essay, in the “Cambridge Companion,” on the will to power. In Nietzsche’s
reading, the Greek mentality abhorred the idea of an Alleinherrschaft, a
“domination by one.” The Athenian institution of ostracism originated in the
need to expel individuals who threatened the balance of power. As Hatab
observes, the rite of the agon “rules out violence, because violence is
actually an impulse to eliminate conflict by annihilating or incapacitating an
opponent.” In “Ecce Homo,” Nietzsche writes, “I attack only a winner.” He goes
after the most tyrannical, domineering forces—hence, his critiques of God and
Wagner.
The
relevance for the modern democratic state is clear. James Madison’s vision of
constitutional checks and balances, of divided powers in equilibrium, is
agonistic politics in action. When one entity gathers too much power, the
system ceases to function. Nietzsche’s political philosophy would appear to
hope for such an outcome, but in “Human, All Too Human” he performs a typical
backtracking maneuver. Having forecast the death of the state, he adds, “To
work toward the diffusion and realization of this idea is admittedly something
else.” The enterprise could lead to “destructive experiments.” It is a good
thing, then, that, in all likelihood, “the state will still persist for a good
while yet.”
Behind
Nietzsche’s array of extreme positions is a much less alarming belief: that the
only healthy state for humanity is one in which rival perspectives vie with one
another, with none gaining the upper hand. The same attitude governs his
fundamental epistemological position about the nature of truth. Each competitor
in the agon is expected to stake his or her claims on truth; Nietzsche advanced
his own opinions with utmost vehemence. The ultimate truth is that no claim
should achieve dominion over all others. As Richard Rorty maintained, Nietzsche
can be understood as a particularly flamboyant kind of pragmatist. We don’t
think of William James as a “dangerous mind,” and yet he, too, said, “Damn the
Absolute!”
Whenever
I feel bewildered by endless interpretive skirmishes over the philosophical
Antichrist, I return to Alexander Nehamas’s “Nietzsche: Life as Literature,”
which appeared in 1985 and retains a commanding place on the near-infinite
Nietzsche bookshelf. Nehamas, a Greek-American thinker steeped in classical
studies, essentially made a virtue of Bertrand Russell’s dismissal of
Nietzsche. The contradictions in Nietzsche’s writings cohere, Nehamas writes,
if we look at him as a literary figure who worked within a philosophical
context, and who crafted a persona that functions as a literary character of
novelistic complexity.
The
disparity between the living Nietzsche and the written one was indeed drastic.
He was a fragile, sensitive, gentle person with elegant manners, constantly
striving to mask his inner turmoil and physical distress. He let his personal
anguish be reflected in a universal predicament: how can we hold to our
convictions in the face of chaos, conflict, decay, and death? The idea of the
eternal return—the prospect of having to live one’s life over and over, every
detail repeated, every pain alongside every joy—becomes all the more potent
when one thinks about having to relive that life, to its terrible end.
Nietzsche
remains a heroic figure in intellectual history because his lonely, desperate
quest seems to join up with so many other expeditions of the mind and soul.
Wherever you travel, in sunny climates or in the shadowlands, Nietzsche has
gone before you. Such is the temper of what may be the most openhearted and
unproblematic passage in all of his writings—the closing aphorism of “Dawn,”
perhaps his most beautiful book:
All these bold birds who fly
out into the wide, widest open—it is true! At some point they will not be able
to fly any farther and will squat down on some pylon or sparse crag—and very
grateful for this miserable accommodation to boot! But who would want to
conclude from this that there was no longer a vast and prodigious trajectory
ahead of them, that they had flown as far and wide as one could fly! All our
great mentors and precursors have finally come to a stop, and it is hardly the
noblest and most graceful of gestures with which fatigue comes to a stop: it
will also happen to you and me! Of what concern, however, is that to you and
me! Other birds will fly farther!
Nietzsche’s
Eternal Return. By Alex Ross. The New Yorker, October 7,
2019.
Has ever
the discrepancy between a man’s thought and person been greater than in
Friedrich Nietzsche? The high-altitude prophet of the Übermensch, the walrus-mustachioed
eulogist of God, the trumpeter of eternal return was, in person, kind,
courteous, and impeccably well mannered. At a pension in Nice, he was
affectionately known as the “dear, half-blind professor.” Julius Paneth, a
Viennese zoologist, described him as “very simple and natural […] he bore no
trace of pomposity or prophetic bearing.” When the feminist intellectual Lou
Andreas-Salomé first met him, she found him entirely unremarkable: a man of
medium height, simply but carefully clothed, with plain, brown hair and a large
mustache. He spoke and even laughed softly, bending his shoulders slightly.
Still, there was something about the man that set him apart. “One could only
with difficulty imagine this figure within a crowd,” she wrote. “He gave the
impression of standing aside, of standing alone.”
This
was, as Stefan Zweig wrote, the tragedy of Nietzsche’s life: that it was a
one-man show, a monodrama “wherein no other actor entered upon the stage.” The
deeper and more demanding Nietzsche’s thinking became, the more his readership
dwindled in size. The Birth of Tragedy (1872), his first book, sold 625 copies
in six years; the three parts of Thus Spoke Zarathustra, published between 1883
and 1885, sold fewer than a hundred copies each. Not until it was too late did
his works finally reach a few decisive ears, including Edvard Munch, August
Strindberg, and the Danish-Jewish critic Georg Brandes, whose lectures at the
University of Copenhagen first introduced Nietzsche’s philosophy to a wider
audience. By then, Nietzsche’s descent into madness had already begun. In his
final letter to Brandes, he signed himself: “The Crucified.”
As we
learn from Sue Prideaux’s masterful new biography, I Am Dynamite!: A Life of
Nietzsche, the German thinker’s solitude was partly forced on him by his
debilitating health. Insomnia, jaundice, vomiting, hemorrhoids, blindness,
crippling headaches, wrecked bowels, chronic exhaustion — I Am Dynamite!
sometimes reads like a calamitous medical record. Yet in spite of his deteriorating
health and accelerating insanity, Friedrich Nietzsche somehow managed to drag
himself and his trunk of books over the mountains of Europe, writing in short
bursts of intense self-discipline the philosophical texts for which he is now
known. “He ranged like Promotheus over the high places,” Prideaux writes, “but
his ascent always had to stop short of the greatest heights, where the bright
light of the eternal snows pierced his eyes like bared swords, as he noted down
his thoughts toward the next book.”
What
sets Prideaux’s biography apart from previous accounts of Nietzsche’s life is
its vibrant intimacy. Eschewing philosophical rigorousness for human proximity,
Prideaux quite simply gets closer to Nietzsche than anyone before her. The
Zarathustrian mask falls away and the vulnerable human is bared. We are
permitted to see how his ideas, his style, grew from the feeble timber of his
physical being. Nietzsche recognized this essential relationship, of course. In
Beyond Good and Evil, he writes that philosophy is “a confession on the part of
its author and a kind of involuntary and unconscious memoir.” Nietzsche wanted
his readers to know this also, to see through the prejudice of philosophers,
his own included. “You had not yet sought yourselves: and you found me,”
Zarathustra says to his disciples. “Now I bid you lose me and find yourselves.”
¤
Nietzsche
was born in 1844 in Röcken, 15 miles south of Leipzig in the eastern German
state of Saxony. His father, Karl Ludwig Nietzsche, a local pastor and former
court tutor, was a meticulous man and gifted pianist admired for his Bach
recitals. But he suffered from a mysterious nervous disorder that increasingly
affected both his eyesight and his power of speech. He died in 1849, just 35
years old. In Ecce Homo, Nietzsche described him as “delicate, lovable and
morbid, like a being destined to pay this world only a passing visit.” He
noted, too, that the age of his father’s death was the same age at which he
began to suffer himself. As Prideaux explains, interest in the cause of Karl
Ludwig’s death has for this reason been considerable, though the exact nature
of the degenerative brain disease he suffered from is not known.
Nietzsche
was expected to follow in his father’s pastoral footsteps, and during his
school years there was no reason to suggest he wouldn’t. He attended
Schulpforta — “the foremost classical school in the German Bund” — and there
distinguished himself as a student and musician, singing in the school choir
and dazzling his peers with his improvisations on the piano. He excelled in
Greek and Latin, and in his final year wrote a philological paper in Latin on
the Greek poet Theognis of Megara that was considered exceptionally brilliant.
When he graduated in 1864, he was said to have been “the most gifted pupil that
Pforta has ever had.”
Nietzsche’s
work ethic was impressive, given the growing catalog of physical afflictions he
had to endure. On at least 20 occasions during his time at Pforta he was
admitted to the sick ward where, Prideaux writes, his various headaches and
stomach pains were treated with leeches “fastened to his earlobes to suck blood
from his head.” He was put to bed in darkened rooms, wore smoked glasses to
shield his eyes from the daylight, and was predicted by the school doctor to
one day suffer total blindness. “At every age of my life,” Nietzsche later
wrote, “suffering, monstrous suffering, was my lot.”
After
Pforta there followed two semesters at the University of Bonn, where Nietzsche
joined a student fraternity, Franconia, whose members were known to frequent
the brothels of Cologne. It was during this time that, as legend stubbornly has
it, Nietzsche contracted syphilis, the alleged cause of his mental breakdown.
When he was first admitted to an asylum, in 1889, he told the doctors that he’d
“infected himself twice,” though as Prideaux observes, he was probably
referring to gonorrhea, not syphilis: “Had they looked at his medical records,
they would have discovered that he had gonorrhea twice, a fact he admitted to
doctors while still in his right mind.”
In 1865,
Nietzsche left Bonn for Leipzig University, where he founded the Classical
Society and began giving well-attended talks on philology, a dry subject he
brought to zesty life. Four years later, the University of Basel in Switzerland
offered him the post of Professor of Classical Philology, a remarkable
achievement for a 24-year-old. But even as he accepted it, Nietzsche knew it was
not a profession to which he was entirely suited. “I would like to be something
more than a drillmaster for competent philologists,” he wrote to his friend
Carl von Gersdorff. “To permeate my discipline with this new blood, to transmit
to my listeners that Schopenhauerian seriousness which is stamped upon the
brows of the sublime man, this is my wish, my daring hope.” To Erwin Rohde, a
friend from his Leipzig days, he wrote: “I am gradually habituating myself to
being a philosopher.”
The
single most important event of Nietzsche’s tenure as a professor was his
friendship with Richard Wagner, at the time Europe’s most celebrated composer.
They had first met in November 1868 at the home of Wagner’s sister, where they
had a long conversation about Schopenhauer, whom they both admired. Then in his
mid-50s, the German composer was living in Tribschen with his second wife,
Cosima, just 50 miles south of Basel. He invited the young philologist to come
visit them. “During the course of the next three years,” Prideaux writes,
“[Nietzsche] would visit Tribschen twenty-three times.” It was, he later
admitted, the happiest time of his life.
But all
the impassioned conversations and happy domesticity could not conceal the
principal differences between them. Wagner was an antisemite, a Francophobe,
and a German nationalist. “I am the most German person,” he wrote in his diary,
“I am the German spirit.” Nietzsche, on the other hand, was “a bad German, but
a good European,” as he himself put it. His experiences as a medical orderly
during the Franco-Prussian War anaesthetized him to the supposed virtues of
Prussian military might. Tending to the thousands of wounded scattered across
the battlefields of Wörth, Hagenau, and Nancy, Nietzsche was repulsed by what
he saw. He feared the bellicose nationalist mood would triumph over culture and
intellect. “Deutschland, Deutschland über alles was, I fear, the end of German
philosophy,” he wrote in The Twilight of Idols. Indeed, he gave up his Prussian
citizenship in order to teach at Basel so he wouldn’t risk being called up for
military service. For the rest of his life, he remained stateless.
A
nascent trend in the Second German Reich that Nietzsche especially abhorred was
antisemitism. It was an essential part of German nationalism in the 19th
century and widely espoused by influential historians like Heinrich Treitschke
and Friedrich Rühs. (Rühs once suggested that Jews ought to wear a yellow patch
on their dress to better identify them.) Ever the individualist, Nietzsche
recognized antisemitism as a trope of the herd animal, of the intellectually
lazy German for whom he had so much contempt. “[It] would perhaps be a good
idea,” he wrote in Beyond Good and Evil, “to eject the anti-Semitic ranters
from the country.” In 1889, when he had already gone insane, he wrote to his
friend Franz Overbeck: “I am just having all anti-Semites shot…”
The
awful irony of Nietzsche’s anti-nationalism and good-Europeanism is that his
sister, Elisabeth, ended up marrying Bernhard Förster, an antisemitic crackpot
who in 1883 immigrated to Paraguay and founded Nueva Germania, a racially pure
German colony. He was, Sue Prideaux writes, “a fanatical proselytizer for
open-air hiking, vegetarianism, the health-giving properties of gymnastics, and
the abolition of alcohol and vivisection.” (Why are fascists always
teetotalers?) Nietzsche thought him monomaniacal and intellectually mediocre.
How was he going to start a colony in the jungle if he didn’t eat meat? he
teasingly asked his sister. When Elisabeth and Bernhard sent him money one year
for Christmas, he cheerfully informed them he’d been so happy he immediately
found a cafe and drank “three very large glasses of a sweet local wine and got
a bitzeli drunk.” When he learned that Bernhard Förster’s nickname for
Elisabeth was “Eli,” he sarcastically remarked to her that Eli means God in
Hebrew.
Still,
Nietzsche loved his sister dearly. He knew Elisabeth was “an intelligent female
and he treated her as such.” When he was still a student, he had attempted to encourage
her independence of thought. He showed her the process by which he himself had
begun to question his faith. “If we had believed since youth that all salvation
came not from Jesus but from another — say, from Mohammed — is it not certain
that we would have enjoyed the same blessings?” he asked. He wanted to show her
how believers deduce from their own inner experience the infallibility of their
faith: “Every true faith is indeed infallible; it performs what the believing
person hopes to find in it, but it does not offer the least support for the
establishing of an objective truth.” Not that he sugarcoated the alternatives
either. “If you want to achieve peace of mind and happiness, then have faith;
if you want to be a disciple of truth, then search.”
He
wasn’t kidding: Nietzsche’s own search for the truth never once gave him either
happiness or peace of mind. During his time as a medical orderly, he had fallen
dangerously ill and was diagnosed with both dysentery and diphtheria. “He was
treated with silver nitrate, opium, and tannic acid enemas,” Prideaux writes,
“the normal treatment of the time, the effect of which was to ruin the
patient’s intestines for life.” In the years to come, his health only
deteriorated further. He began to rely on friends to help him read, engaged
Elisabeth to help keep house for him, and in 1876–’77 took a year’s leave of
absence from the University of Basel. In 1879, he finally resigned. He sold his
possessions, entrusted his financial affairs to his friend Franz Overbeck, and
like Zarathustra himself “went into the mountains” to enjoy his spirit and
solitude. “I live as if the centuries were nothing,” he wrote to a friend, “and
I pursue my thoughts without thinking of the date and of the newspapers.”
For the
10 years of sane life he had left, the stateless Nietzsche was in a
near-constant state of nomadic wandering. He had no luck in love, only very few
friends, and virtually no readers. His headaches and vomiting sometimes kept
him incapacitated for as many as 30 days straight. He couldn’t eat or sleep,
and increasingly relied on powders of chloral hydrate to relieve his insomnia.
But incorrect doses of this drug, Prideaux notes, produced “nausea, vomiting,
hallucinations, confusion, convulsions, breathing and heart irregularities: all
the symptoms, in fact, that Nietzsche was taking it to relieve.”
And yet
he only seemed to become more prolific, more ambitious. He boldly took it upon
himself to reevaluate all of Western philosophy, to think through the moral and
religious prejudice that has kept us from seeking the truth — or, perhaps, kept
the truth hidden from us. For Nietzsche believed that Western philosophy from
the time of Socrates on had been an enormous misunderstanding, an epic blunder.
Centuries of Christian morality had led to the current crisis of decadence and
nihilism by teaching us to combat our instincts and exterminate our passions.
Like Schopenhauer, Nietzsche believed life was dominated by irrational impulses
and animal desires, by a blind, ceaseless will to live. But where Schopenhauer
could see only meaninglessness and suffering, and thus resigned himself to
pessimism, Nietzsche affirmed the will to live. “We others, we immoralists,” he
wrote, “have on the contrary opened wide our hearts to every kind of
understanding, comprehension, approval. We do not readily deny, we seek our
honor in affirming.”
For
Nietzsche, nihilism is not a belief in nothing, but a refusal to believe in
what is. Christianity, by redirecting our gaze away from our animal existence
toward some illusory divine harmony, was therefore nihilistic, hostile to life:
Christianity
has taken the side of everything weak, base, ill-constituted, it has made an
ideal out of opposition to the preservative instincts of strong life; it has
depraved the reason even of the intellectually strongest natures by teaching
men to feel the supreme values of intellectuality as sinful, as misleading, as
temptations.
What is
still thrilling about Nietzsche’s agon with God and Christianity is the fact
that he was not a disinterested party. He knew that God’s death was not a
deliverance into serene, rational light but a profoundly disruptive and
disorienting experience that would make great demands of humanity. He valued
strength, will, courage, and power because he knew the task that lay ahead was
a serious one. “Christianity is a system,” he writes in Twilight of the Idols,
“a consistently thought out and complete view of things. If one breaks out of
it a fundamental idea, the belief in God, one thereby breaks the whole thing to
pieces: one has nothing of any consequence left in one’s hands.” As a result of
God’s death, all of morality will have to be dismantled, razed to the ground.
Nothing less than a revaluation of all values is required.
This is
where many of Nietzsche’s readers, I imagine, begin to fidget and shift a
little in their seats, looking around for an excuse not to go on reading. For
his attempts at filling the void left by God, his affirmation of life and the
will to live, his theory of eternal recurrence and deification of the
individual free spirit (the Übermensch), can often sound hyperbolic,
self-aggrandizing, or simply insane. Nietzsche thought so himself. “He who
knows how to breathe the air of my writings knows that it is an air of the
heights, a robust air,” he writes in Ecce Homo. “One has to be made for it,
otherwise there is no small danger one will catch cold.”
¤
In his
engaging new memoir-essay, Hiking with Nietzsche: On Becoming Who You Are, the
American philosopher John Kaag makes an impassioned effort to breathe that air,
to scale those forbidding heights and peer into the post-Christian abyss. He
takes seriously Nietzsche’s claim that in order understand him “one must be
accustomed to living on mountains.”
Kaag’s
book opens with an account of a journey he made as a 19-year-old philosophy
student to Sils-Maria in Switzerland, where he spent several weeks hiking the
same terrain Nietzsche knew so well: Splügen, Piz Corvatsch, Val Fex, the
Julier Pass. Kaag stays overnight at the same boardinghouse where the German
philosopher summered in the 1880s. He hikes for up to 15 hours a day, a copy of
Nietzsche’s writings always at hand. On one occasion, he spends a cold night
camping in the mountains, alone in the utter blackness. The temperature plunged
so low frostbite left a permanent scar on his earlobe.
“Thirty-one
days dilated, compressed, and slipped away,” Kaag recalls. “I stopped eating
and sleeping. My hair grew shaggy and my pants loose.” His mother tells him he
sounds “a little off” on the phone. Alone with Nietzsche’s writings, he comes
close to suicide, lulled into a sense of vertigo by the peaks, gorges, and
chasms all around him. He recalls Nietzsche’s words from Beyond Good and Evil:
“And when you gaze long into an abyss the abyss also gazes into you.” In the
end, fortunately, he chickens out, as he puts it. On his last evening in
Sils-Maria he breaks down, goes to a grand old hotel nearby, and splurges on a
sumptuous six-course dinner.
Almost
two decades later, Kaag returns to Sils-Maria with his wife, the Kantian
philosopher Carol Hay, and their three-year-old daughter. In the intervening
years, Kaag has become a professor of philosophy at the University of
Massachusetts Lowell, written a highly regarded book on American transcendental
philosophy, and largely left his youthful Zarathustrian mania behind. But when
he starts teaching a seminar on Nietzsche, the old demons begin to stir: “[O]n
quiet nights, after a day of teaching Nietzsche, the high peaks once again
began to beckon.” At his wife’s suggestion, the little family makes the trip to
Switzerland together.
Kaag’s
account of his return to Sils-Maria and of his reunion with the philosophical
idol of his youth is an engrossing one. Now closer to middle age than his
teenage years, he realizes that Nietzsche’s writings are actually “uniquely
fitted” for adulthood. “Nietzsche’s philosophy is sometimes pooh-poohed as
juvenile — the product of a megalomaniac that is perhaps well suited to the
self-absorption and naïveté of the teenage years,” he writes. But Nietzsche’s
task was “wakefulness itself,” as he put it, and when do we need that most
urgently if not when we have begun to settle down? “At nineteen, on the summit
of Corvatsch, I had no idea how dull the world could sometimes be,” Kaag
writes. “How easy it would be to remain in the valleys, to be satisfied with
mediocrity. Or how difficult it would be to stay alert to life. At thirty-six,
I am just now beginning to understand.”
Hiking
with Nietzsche serves as a straightforward and even practical introduction to
the German philosopher’s writings, and makes a convincing case for why they
continue to matter. Even readers not necessarily tempted to descend into the
Nietzschean abyss will surely find Kaag’s exploration of selfhood, decadence,
companionship, and physical duress both invigorating and thought-provoking.
Contrary to the how-to-live-your-life genre, and in keeping with Nietzsche’s
explosive and discomforting ideas, Kaag manages to ask all the right questions
without irritably reaching for any palliative answers or solutions. Reflecting
on Nietzsche’s beloved aphorism, become what you are, Kaag remarks:
The
enduring nature of being human is to turn into something else, which should not
be confused with going somewhere else. This may come as a great disappointment
to one who goes in search of the self. What one is, essentially, is this active
transformation, nothing more, nothing less. This is not a grand wisdom quest or
hero’s journey, and it doesn’t require one to escape to the mountains.
Above
all, Kaag’s portrait of Nietzsche, like Sue Prideaux’s, is a deeply moving one.
Walking in his footsteps, he shows us the heights to which Nietzsche rose and
the depths to which he sank, the sacrifices he made and the suffering he
endured. “He continued to want, and now imagine, more than he could ever have,”
Kaag writes in what is perhaps the most insightful and devastating observation
in this elegant, incisive book.
The
importance of these intimate, deeply human portraits of Nietzsche cannot be
overstated. The identification of his thought with fascism and Nazism endures.
After his storied breakdown in Turin in 1889, Nietzsche remained a mental
invalid until his death in 1900. For most of those years, he was left in the
care of his sister, Elisabeth Förster-Nietzsche, fresh from her Aryan debacle
in Paraguay where, after their colony had predictably been splintered by
disagreements and fraud, her husband had taken his life. For the next four
decades, Elisabeth tried to shape and control her brother’s posthumous legacy
in a way that suited her racist and nationalist sympathies. In her own writings
during World War I, she encouraged the cruelest misinterpretations of
Nietzsche’s thought, portraying him as a conservative, militant patriot. Later
still, Elisabeth happily allowed National Socialists to join her in the
Nietzsche archive and aid in preparing his texts for new editions. Among them
was the philosopher Alfred Bäumler, who helped orchestrate the book burnings in
Berlin’s Opera Square in May 1933. Adolf Hitler, too, was a guest of the
Nietzsche archive. In 1933, incredibly, Elisabeth presented him with
Nietzsche’s walking stick.
The
philosophical sanitation of Nietzsche’s ideas undertaken by Walter Kaufmann
from the 1950s on is not yet complete. Deliberate misinterpretations are still
with us. We need only look to the Harvard psychologist Steven Pinker, in whose
recent book Enlightenment Now Nietzsche is portrayed as a philosophical
monster. “Nietzsche argued that it’s good to be a callous, egoistic,
megalomaniacal sociopath,” Pinker writes. Cherry-picking quotes from
prejudicially scanned writings, he attempts to show that Nietzsche was a
proto-Nazi: “The connections between Nietzsche’s ideas and the megadeath
movements of the 20th century are obvious enough: a glorification of violence
and power, an eagerness to raze the institutions of liberal democracy, a
contempt for most of humanity, and a stone-hearted indifference to human life.”
Ironically,
like the Nazis before him, Pinker ascribes beliefs to Nietzsche that would have
horrified the philosopher. But just as Nietzsche has already debunked the
positivistic liberalism still espoused by Pinker, so he knew that people would
abuse and misrepresent his ideas. “I am frightened by the thought of what
unqualified and unsuitable people may invoke my authority one day,” he wrote.
“Yet that is the torment of every great teacher of mankind: he knows that,
given the circumstances and the accidents, he can become a disaster as well as
a blessing to mankind.” Nietzsche seems always to have had the last word. In
that sense, too, he was a truly posthumous man.
The
Sufferings of Nietzsche. By Morten Høi Jensen. Los Angeles Review of Books,
December 5, 2018.
Friedrich
Nietzsche, Karl Marx and Charles Darwin are the great triumvirate of
19th-century thinkers whose ideas still have huge impact today. Nietzsche was
philosophy’s supreme iconoclast; his sayings include “God is dead” and “There
are no facts, only interpretations”. Highly relevant, yet his association with
concepts such as the Übermensch, master morality, slave morality and, possibly
most dangerous, the will to power, have also contributed to him being widely
misinterpreted. There are three myths in particular that need dynamiting: that
his politics were on the far right, he was a misogynist and he lacked a sense
of humour.
Misappropriation
has been rife. Richard Spencer, a leader of America’s “alt-right”, claims to
have been “red-pilled by Nietzsche”, while Jordan Peterson quotes extensively
from him. But let’s start with the Nazis. Growing up in Bismarck’s reich, there
were three things Nietzsche hated: the big state, nationalism and antisemitism.
“Deutschland, Deutschland über alles, that is the end of German philosophy,” he
wrote, and “I will have all antisemites shot.”
His
sister Elisabeth held contrasting views. She married a notorious antisemite
agitator (Nietzsche refused to go to the wedding), and the couple went off to
Paraguay to found a New Germany of “pure-blooded” Aryan colonists. By the time
the colony failed in 1889, Nietzsche had lost his reason. Elisabeth returned to
Germany, where she took charge of her brother, gathered up all his papers and
founded the Nietzsche Archive.
When it
came to faking news, Elisabeth was a pioneer. On her brother’s death in 1900,
Elisabeth didn’t think his death mask was sufficiently impressive, so she faked
a second one. She did the same to his writing, rummaging about in his literary
estate, cutting and pasting at will. She published an unreliable biography of
him and delayed publication of his autobiography, Ecce Homo, until she had
deleted uncomplimentary references to herself.
Nietzsche
was always very sparing in what he published, but he loved playing around with
book titles. He wrote many more titles than books. One he scrapped was The Will
to Power. He scrawled a shopping list on the abandoned title page. But
Elisabeth took fragments from here and there, concocted a book called The Will
to Power and published it under her brother’s name. It was such a success that
a few years later she published a greatly expanded edition.
Elisabeth
lived until 1935. This gave her almost 40 years to doctor texts and letters and
manipulate the literary estate. The Nietzsche Archive became an institution
filled with extreme rightwingers, whose aggressive nationalism chimed with her
own.Among them were Oswald Spengler, and Alfred Bäumler, who oversaw book
burning in Berlin and prepared Nietzsche’s texts for new editions, including
another The Will to Power that again gave the impression the text had been
authored by Nietzsche himself. Bäumler was joined as editor in the Nietzsche
Archive by Martin Heidegger. The two of them took the extraordinary view that
Nietzsche’s published works hardly counted because the real philosophy resided
in the Nachlass, the unpublished literary estate that Elisabeth had already
manipulated to her own ends. This allowed them to continue jigsawing dislocated
fragments to put their own ideas into Nietzsche’s mouth.
Elisabeth
greatly admired Mussolini. In 1932 she persuaded the Weimar National theatre to
put on a play written by him. Hitler showed up during the performance and
presented her with a huge bouquet of flowers. A year later, now chancellor of
Germany, he visited the Nietzsche Archive, carrying his customary whip. He
remained for an hour and a half. When he emerged the whip had gone. In its
place he grasped Nietzsche’s walking stick, presented to him by Elisabeth.
Hitler
was infatuated with the idea of himself as the philosopher leader. It is
impossible to prove whether he studied Nietzsche; it is widely believed he did
not. The surviving books from his library during his time in prison in 1924,
when he wrote Mein Kampf, do not include any works by Nietzsche. It must be
possible they were part of his book collection at the time and have since been
lost but his later library preserves no well-thumbed copies. The notorious film
of the 1934 Nuremberg rally was given the deliberately Nietzschean title
Triumph of the Will, but when the director, Leni Riefenstahl, asked Hitler
whether he liked to read Nietzsche, he answered: “No, I can’t really do much
with Nietzsche … he is not my guide.”
The
complicated ideas contained in the books were of no use to him, but catch
phrases such as “the blond beast”, the Übermensch (neither of which is a racial
concept) and “beyond good and evil” could be put to infinite misuse. Yet even
as Nazi propagandists and phrasemongers usurped Nietzsche’s words and meaning,
some among them realised the absurdity. Ernst Krieck, a prominent Nazi
ideologue, sarcastically remarked that apart from the fact that Nietzsche was
not a socialist, not a nationalist and opposed to racial thinking, he might have
been a leading National Socialist thinker.
Nietzsche
also has an undeserved reputation as a misogynist. Born in 1844, he attended
one of the best schools in Europe while Elisabeth was sent to Fräulein
Paraski’s institution to be taught how to capture a husband, run a household
and speak just sufficient French to be considered elegant but not (God forbid)
learned. Yet Nietzsche treated Elisabeth as an equal. He gave her reading
lists, urged her to think for herself and widen her knowledge by attending
public lectures.
In 1874,
when he was professor of philology at Basel University, a vote was taken on the
admission of women to the university. Nietzsche was one of only four who voted
in favour, and the motion was lost.
In 1876,
he travelled to Italy to join Malwida von Meysenbug, a feminist who campaigned
vigorously for the emancipation of women. Meysenbug had been exiled from
Germany for smuggling letters during the revolution of 1848, after which she
settled among the political exiles in north London, working as a tutor.
Malwida’s reputation was such that when Garibaldi sailed up the Thames in 1864,
he summoned her to talk politics over breakfast on his yacht. Malwida was
starstruck by Garibaldi’s Pirates of the Caribbean glamour as he lowered an upholstered
armchair to winch her comfortably up onto the deck for their breakfast meeting.
Nietzsche
and Meysenbug intended to found a school for free spirits in the caves beneath
Sorrento.The free spirits were to include women and nothing would be off limits
in their study of culture, philosophy, aesthetics, religious scepticism and
sexual freedom. The school never materialised but his friendship with Meysenbug
widened Nietzsche’s feminist circle to include Meta von Salis-Marschlins, an
activist for women’s suffrage, and Resa von Schirnhofer.
By the
1880s, women were allowed into the university lecture theatre as Hörerin,
“listeners”. Nietzsche encouraged his sister, Salis-Marschlins and Schirnhofer
to apply. In 1887, Salis-Marschlins became the first woman to gain a PhD from a
Swiss university. Schirnhofer followed suit. Both gained their doctorates in
philosophy.
In 1882,
Nietzsche fell completely and drastically in love with Lou Salomé, who would
later enchant both Rilke and Freud. During this period, he wrote about the
psychological dilemma of women. In The Gay Science, he notes how monstrous it
is that young women are told that sex is shameful and sinful, only to be hurled
into marriage and propelled by the man they are taught to worship as a god into
the terror and duty of sex. How are they expected to cope? “There,” he
observes, “one has tied a psychic knot that has no equal.”
I had no
idea Nietzsche could be funny until I read his letters. “The gentlest, most
reasonable man may, if he wears a large moustache, sit as it were in its shade
and feel safe,” he wrote, self-mockingly. “As the accessory of a large
moustache he will give the impression of being military, irascible and
sometimes violent – and will be treated accordingly.”
Condemned
by ill health and abysmal eyesight to convey his philosophy in short,
aphoristic bursts, Nietzsche knew the power of raising a bubble of laughter,
only to puncture it as you ponder the further meaning: “Is man God’s mistake,
or is God man’s mistake?” “Man does not strive for happiness; only the
Englishman does that” – a dig at Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill.
“Possession usually diminishes the possession.” “Never trust a thought that
occurs to you indoors.” He even makes fun of his readers: “The worst readers
are those who behave like plundering troops: they take away a few things they
can use, dirty and confound the remainder, and revile the whole.”
Nietzsche
is an unusual philosopher because he doesn’t tell us what to think. There’s no
such thing as Nietzsche-ism. He sums it up in one of his aphorisms: “You repay
a teacher badly by becoming merely a pupil.” In other words, read me but think
further.
As for
the myths that have grown up around him, the last word surely should belong to
the man himself. “I am frightened,” he wrote, “by the thought of what
unqualified and unsuitable people may invoke my authority one day. Yet that is
the torment of every teacher … he knows that, given the circumstances and
accidents, he can become a disaster as well as a blessing to mankind.”
Far
right, misogynist, humourless? Why Nietzsche is misunderstood. By Sue Prideaux.The Guardian , October 6,
2018.
Also of interest :
Friedrich
Nietzsche knew his controversial philosophy was “dynamite,” but his work wasn’t
appreciated until after he descended into madness. His megalomaniac sister
Elisabeth, who had a penchant for National Socialism and deceitfulness, took
control of his work, exploiting and manipulating it. Antisemite ideology
disgusted Nietzsche, yet ironically Elisabeth left him with a false antisemitic
reputation that still lingers.
It’s a
tragic story, but now that Elisabeth’s interference has been untangled,
Nietzsche’s work seems to be more popular than ever, if new books such as
Hiking with Nietzsche by John Kaag and the seven-way bidding war for the
manuscript of Sue Prideaux’s biography titled I Am Dynamite! are any
indication. Prideaux’s investigation illuminates Nietzsche as a brilliant man
of polar extremes with a sense of humor and despair, an ability not to take
himself too seriously, a love of both Apollonian and Dionysian aspects of life,
and many love-hate relationships — with his sister, mother, Richard Wagner, Lou
Salomé, and others.
“The
Weightiest Questions in the Smallest Number of Words”: Retelling the Nietzsche
Story
Skye C.
Cleary interviews Sue Prideaux. Los Angeles Review of Books, October 24, 2018.
No comments:
Post a Comment