Popular
culture is replete with cartoonish
depictions of Nazism. Hitler seems to emerge suddenly, as if he had been
waiting in the wings as a fait accompli. One moment it’s Weimar decadence,
really good art, and Stormtroopers and communists fighting in the streets. The
next, Hindenburg is handing Adolf the keys to the kingdom and it’s all
torchlight parades, Triumph of the Will, and plaintive Itzhak Perlman violins.
Hitler rises above a reborn Reich as a kind of totalitarian god. All aspects of
life come under his control through the Nazi Party’s complete domination of
German life. Of course, this is not really how it worked.
Before
Hitler achieved his genocidal powers, there were years of what we would now
call “intense partisan bickering,” decreasing prosperity, and violence in the
streets. In the end, Hitler cobbled together a rickety coalition of
business-minded technocrats, traditional conservatives, military interests, and
his own radical ethno-nationalists into a plausible government. As the new government
consolidated its power, thousands of communists and trade unionists were
subjected to harsh suppression and were among the first to be shipped away to
what would eventually become the concentration camps. And yet for a time, life
for the overwhelming majority of Germans — even briefly for German Jews — went
on largely as it had in the Weimar era. There was clearly a new regime in town,
but most Germans got up in the mornings in the mid-to-late 1930s and went to
work, just as they had in the 1920s. January through March of 1933 was not
1776, 1789, 1791, 1917, or even 1979. Far from the world turning upside down,
things were strangely continuous for many Germans as though nothing much had
happened at all. For a few Germans, things were astoundingly better.
With the
global rise of demagogues of the far right like Donald Trump, Marine Le Pen,
Viktor Orbán, Narendra Modi, and Recep Tayyip Erdoğan, “fascism” is on the tip
of everyone’s tongues. Water-cooler conversations turn around these strongmen
or strongmen-in-waiting and their potential to tower over the political
landscape of the 21st century. Second- and thirdhand versions of Hannah Arendt
and Theodor Adorno have become a welcome addition to the American media
landscape. We are all deeply invested in the ideology and psychology of
fascism.
Yet, for
all this talk of fascism in the air, it’s remarkable how much we have come to
accept predominantly ideological and psychological — as opposed to formally
political and economic — frames for our arguments. Few people want to talk
about how fascist societies like Nazi Germany actually functioned, how they
were built, who made them work, and why. But when we do, a much sharper image
emerges, in which an idiosyncratic economic and political structure is more
clearly visible.
In Nazi
Germany, economic history shows us a rapid change in the distribution of income
and the emergence of a managerial elite who obtained an outsized share of
national income, not just the now-proverbial one percent, but the top 0.1
percent. These were Nazi Germany’s equivalent to today’s so-called
“supermanagers” (to use Thomas Piketty’s now-famous term). This parallel with
today’s neoliberal society calls for a closer examination of the place of
supermanagers in both regimes, with illuminating and unsettling implications.
Behemoth:
The Political Economy of Nazism
Thinkers
like Adorno and Arendt tended to approach Nazism through the lens of
philosophy. They accepted Nazi self-assertions of “totalitarianism”; that a
total, unified society was bound together through identification with party and
leader, that all was driven through a Volksgemeinschaft (national community, or
the consciousness of being part of an “authentic” national community). The
reality was considerably messier. Adorno’s colleague Franz Neumann considered
the same questions from the vantages of political economy and law. Far from
“state capitalism,” where the profit motive is eliminated and production is
under the complete control of the state, Neumann noted that under Nazism, business
— especially large corporate interests — was given extraordinary leeway. They
did not have perfect free rein, but large business interests were relieved of
many previous social democratic restrictions. Independent labor organizations
were crushed, and business was allowed to coagulate into massive,
profit-generating monopolies as long as it produced the necessary goods and
services the party and the army required.
The
closer Neumann looked at the day-to-day operations of Nazism, the less
convinced he was that one could call Nazi Germany a “state” in any traditional
sense of the word. Along with his fellow Frankfurt School colleague Otto
Kirchheimer, they noted that power, authority, and responsibility were not, as
propaganda would have it, bound up entirely in the person of the Leader, but
rather were confusingly diffuse throughout a disjointed and irrational system.
Everyone (that is everyone included within the national-racial community) was
to fall in line or develop themselves through Führerprinzip into autonomous
self-starters, entrepreneurs, and pioneers of the national spirit in whatever
sector they worked. Even as a rump state maintained the appearance of a heavy
bureaucracy, with a great deal of actual organization still left to technocrats,
industry was given wide berth. Society was dominated by myriad (in the parlance
of our time) “thought-leaders” with overlapping and competing fiefdoms. The
party itself maintained personnel connections within nearly every sector, and
its own areas of control, particularly over racial questions — the sine qua non
of Nazism. A deal was struck whereby the armed forces, still bruised and
feeling “betrayed” by German surrender from World War I, came to an internal
balance of powers agreement. Hitler was in charge, to be sure, but only through
a constant negotiation between these sectors and their own mini-sovereignties.
And even Hitler wasn’t the sovereign decision maker both his fervent supporters
and adamant critics wanted him to be; Hitler’s office was more of a
clearinghouse, often receiving conflicting positions in, sometimes sending
conflicting positions out to be resolved by some other, smaller leader
elsewhere. Certainly, the Führer was a dictator, but he was first among many,
neither the striding colossus of Nazi propagandists nor the all-powerful,
mini-mustachioed evil of moralistic Western popular culture.
In his
final analysis, Neumann realized that Nazi Germany was not really a state in
any recognizable sense at all. Far from Hobbes’s Biblical Leviathan — a
mechanistic vision of a commonwealth functioning collectively for the safety
and flourishing of its individual subjects whose power is bound up, expressed,
and represented in the person of a monarch or ruling council — Neumann saw in
Nazi Germany Hobbes’s alternative vision, the rumbling horror of the land
monster Behemoth, a beast for Hobbes composed of Oliver Cromwell’s New Model
Army, the Long Parliament, and Puritan businessmen taking on the appearance of
a new state but in reality a mere disjointed assemblage of military, economic,
and even restrictive sexual power that in Hobbes’s analysis spelled out the
essence of anarchy in Britain and the utter devastation of Ireland. The German
Behemoth under Nazi rule was a similar amalgam. Famously, it was only with the
handshake agreements of traditional conservatives, the new far-right
nationalists, the army, and, most importantly, the business elite, that the
Nazis were given a shot at “governing.” Several of the business elite had to
personally petition Hindenburg to appoint Hitler in the first place.
Profits
and Salaries in Dark Times
Neither
Neumann (nor Hobbes for that matter) should be misunderstood. A “behemoth”-like
structure can be highly efficient. Nazi efficiency in disenfranchisement,
slavery, and genocide was unparalleled in terms of their speed and
thoroughness. But such a structure functionally overturns the most basic logic
of the state; it is diffuse sovereignty.
In this
diffuse sovereignty, soaring profits went not simply to the one percent of its
day, but to reinforce the power of a nascent class of executives across
different economic and social sectors. Even while internal regulations on, say,
labor conditions were dismantled, external quotas and quality controls were
implemented. These regulations often had the blessing of business, especially
big business, which used such controls to crowd out small- and medium-sized
firms that could not meet the substantial party, “state,” or military demands.
And this meant that large German business did well. So well, that the only real
Nazi-era restriction (before they were removed altogether at the start of the
war) on profit was a 1934 rate cap of six to eight percent on dividends and
even then, the surplus beyond this was merely redirected into short-term
government bonds which would pay out against the taxes owed by the firm. But,
as Neumann noted of profits in the Nazi-era, “profits are not identical with
dividends. Profits are, above all, salaries, bonuses, commissions for special
services, over-valuated patents, licenses, connections, and good will.” These
profits went to the “supermanagers” of the Third Reich.
Men (and
they were almost always men) like this were the linchpin of Nazi society. After
soaring, inflationary highs during World War I, and an unsurprising loss in the
subsequent crash compounded by the Great Depression, the share of income of the
top one percent in Germany began to return to relatively normal levels during
the Weimar years. But once the Nazis consolidated power, the fortunes of the
Thousand Year Reich’s one percent truly took off. This was particularly the
case for those supermanagers at the very top, the 0.1 percent. From just under
four percent in 1930, their share of the national income under the new Nazi
order would nearly double by the eve of World War II.
In
contrast, during roughly the same period, the United States saw not only a drop
for the top 0.1 percent but a choppy and precipitous one, from above eight
percent before 1930 to below four percent by the middle of World War II. These
figures refer to the top share of labor income alone, excluding return to
capital. Despite similar counter-cyclic spending, whatever was so richly
rewarding for Nazi-era Germans in the highest income group did not correspond
to their American counterparts. This is not peculiar to the United States;
similar trends can be observed in, for example, France and Sweden. A new
“managerial class” appeared in nearly all developed economies, but clearly it
was in some way less valued in social democracies (or for that matter, in the
Soviet Union) than in the new fascist societies.
Over the
last 35 years, our own “neoliberal” society has developed some rather
unexpected parallels with Nazi Germany. In his much celebrated work Capital in
the Twenty-First Century, Thomas Piketty noticed an odd feature of our
contemporary economy: though income inequality levels in the United States are
today similar to those that existed at the beginning of the 20th century, there
has been a change in how high-income earners derive their income. In Piketty’s
overall argument the vast economic growth, stability, and equity of the postwar
to mid-1970s era, the Trente Glorieuses, was due to the historic idiosyncrasy
of rebuilding after the World Wars, pumping economic output in North America,
Europe, and Japan far above where they “naturally” lie at about 2.5 percent.
Yet the general tendency is for the return on capital (historically stable at
around four to five percent) to always exceed the growth of the economy. This
has the distributional consequence of allocating a higher share of national
income to investors (capital income) relative to workers (wages), and will
gradually lead to societies characterized by high income and wealth inequality
(i.e., a kind of neofeudalism). In such societies, it makes more economic sense
to marry into wealth than pursue any kind of a career because income
disparities are primarily driven by inherited wealth and the significant
advantage of earning a return on capital over earned wages. However, the odd
bit that pops up in Piketty concerning our contemporary economic situation is
that the gradual increase in income inequality over the past three decades is
the direct result of a surge in top wages, rather than a revival of capital
income — this is not the “idle rich.”
The
salaries of the top one percent have increased from roughly eight percent of
total income in the 1980s to a staggering 18 percent of total income today.
While wages for the vast majority of Americans have remained largely stagnant
for the past 35 years, the top one percent has seen growth by nearly 140
percent and of that massive income — so large as to actually exceed capital
returns — nearly three-quarters goes to the tiny top 0.1 percent. The bulk of
these “star salaries” do not come from, say, high-earning celebrities (artists,
actors, athletes), but rather from individuals such as corporate executives,
hedge fund managers, university presidents, etc. Piketty calls the individuals
who comprise this top 0.1 percent “supermanagers.”
How do we
explain this explosion in salaries? We could begin with the theory that high
pay reflects a supermanager’s productivity and skills (i.e., large
contributions to corporate profits), yet this does not hold up to scrutiny. To
begin with, there is a very sharp discontinuity of salaries between those at
the very top and those immediately below, where one would have expected a
gradual increase if qualifications or professional experience were the key
driver. Executive pay has been found to rise when sales and profits increase
for reasons that are beyond a manager’s control (e.g., price fluctuations).
Further, given the size and complexity of the modern corporation, it is
difficult to determine what share of a firm’s performance can be directly
linked to the skills of any particular executive manager or officer as opposed
to the rest of workers. Controlled experiments (e.g., determining the
performance of a different manager in the same environment) are impossible.
Assessing performance on the basis of some “objective” measure, such as
shareholder value, also proves difficult.
If “star
salaries” can’t be explained by contribution to the productive enterprise, high
managerial compensation would appear to be what economists call “rent” —
essentially, profit extraction. Managers could quite simply have their “hands
in the till,” or be facilitated in their ability to extract rent through
bargaining power and market power (including a manager’s ability to bring to
the table things that cannot easily be replaced or commoditized, like personal
connections, or to make it costly for any potential replacement to take over).
Piketty concludes that the rent element is probably high, with high pay for
supermanagers an institutional practice shaped by social norms.
In our view there is another way to understand
the rise of the supermanager in terms of value (though in a rather
unconventional sense) produced for the firm. The supermanager is
neoliberalism’s governance mechanism, a way to negotiate and smooth over
differences between sectors of power in society, just as the supermanager avant
la lettre did so in Nazi Germany
Supermanagerial
Governance
Supermanagers
provide a very specific kind of governance needed in very specific kinds of
regimes. The supermanager and their seemingly outsized share of national income
is not merely a phenomenon of our own neoliberal era, from the Reagan/Thatcher
“revolutions” to the Clinton/Blair era. It was a conspicuous feature of Nazi
Germany (and although the data is thinner, it would seem 1920–’30s fascism in general).
The most plausible explanation for this compensation draws not from any
particularly radical theory of value, nor from moralistic parables about
corruption, nor from fairy tales about superheroic capacities. The most
plausible explanation is that supermanagers are paid for governance where the
state has been redeployed elsewhere or, even, effectively dissolved.
One could
think of this as a peculiar kind of rent extraction for the ability to shift
seamlessly at the boundaries of these sectors — from one board, to another,
from a corporation, to a foundation, to a university, to government, to a think
tank and back again. One could think of this in a rather perverse way as real
marginal added value, compensation for the difficult work of governance without
a Rechtsstaat — without a rational, sovereign state, or with a receding or
redistributed one. Seen in this light, the ability to provide political backing
through connections is a highly remunerated component of this type of
governance. What we think of today as the “revolving doors” between corporate
offices, consultancies, government regulatory agencies, think tanks, media,
etc. were part of everyday economic, political, and social life in Nazi
Germany. The heightened and more powerful form of interlocking directorates
commonly observed in advanced capitalist economies were, for the Nazis, highly
formalized as powerful supervisory boards and chambers between sectors and
firms. Firms who were heavily invested in the party before the Nazi takeover (only
about one-seventh of total firms but, taking into account the size of firms,
over half of the total German stock market) saw immediate gains of six to eight
percent by mid-1933 already. Comparable levels of remuneration for direct
political connection are found only in developing and advanced neoliberal
states.
The
parallel between the Nazi “revolution” in the 1930s and the neoliberal
“revolution” in the 1980s and ’90s goes much further. The Nazis were also
pioneers in what was then the uncharted economic waters of “privatization.” In
the face of the Great Depression, states across the world — including the Social
Democratic led Weimar Republic — nationalized key industries and, in some
cases, like Germany, nearly the entirety of the financial sector. The Nazis —
despite early propaganda indicating otherwise — were the unique exception. Not
only did they avoid further nationalization but they innovated a process so
idiosyncratic at the time that it required coining a German neologism:
Reprivatisierung.
Quickly
transferred into English as “reprivatization,” the phenomenon and its
potentially salutary effects were observed by such notable organs of liberal
economic thought as The Economist and mainstream outlets like Time magazine.
Before Margaret Thatcher began the privatization of council housing and long
before welfare reform was a twinkle in Bill Clinton’s eye, the Nazis were
turning heavy industries, nearly the entirety of the financial and banking
sector, and even some social services over to private hands and to new,
innovative public/private hybrids. Even before this process was “enhanced” by
“Aryanizing” previously Jewish held property, rates of privatization were as
high the European average would become some 70 years later when neoliberal
reforms began on the continent.
The
resulting market concentration, the decrease of small businesses and the growth
of monopolies and cartels in Nazi Germany are well documented. It’s no surprise
that supermanagerial governance would go hand in hand with the consolidation of
large industrial and financial interests, as the value it provides is enhanced
when sectors and market power are concentrated. This is another interesting
parallel between the Nazi era and our own. Today we find that antitrust and
intellectual property laws have favored the concentration of market power in a
handful of companies in key sectors such as pharmaceuticals, biotechnology,
media and entertainment, not to mention the financial sector. And we find that
unsurprisingly, today’s supermanagers thrive, in particular, in large,
profitable firms. A recent study finds that during the period 1978–2012, a
large share (two thirds) of wage earnings inequality was driven not just by the
deepening of pay differentials (between those at the very top and the rest of
workers) throughout all firms, but also by the emergence of higher-paying
large, profitable firms.
The
parallels don’t end with political and economic power but stretch,
horrifyingly, into the everyday. As Kirchheimer wrote of the Nazi-era police
force in a report for the OSS in 1945:
The general “task” presumed to have
been given to the police in the Nazi state — that of safeguarding the state and
regime against any disturbance — implies the supremacy of any of its actions
(whether in the form of decree, directive, internal instruction, or pure
action) over any existing law […] Thus, the police becomes “a function whose
activities are determined solely through what is politically necessary […] This
means that the police as such can do whatever it deems necessary, without being
restrained by legal authorities.
Just as it
was for fascists, neoliberals depend on the arbitrary power of the police, only
to be checked, if ever, by post-facto political considerations. Far from
cowering in fear of cartoon Hitler in the 1930s and ’40s or for that matter in
the face of the Constitution today, police are deeply empowered, with almost no
enforceable judicial or legislative check on power. This is the necessary “on
the ground” counterpart — learned well from colonization abroad — to
supermanagerial control of the endlessly complex, newly “marketized” governance
apparati, public-private initiatives, and the labyrinthine overlapping
jurisdictions between sectors in the neoliberal state.
Different
Raisons d’Être
The
numerous parallels between neoliberalism and fascism — particularly when
looking at these kinds of political and economic structures — can tempt
analysts to overstate the case and claim that neoliberalism and fascism are one
and the same. But this downplays the tremendous differences that exist between
these regimes and misses the power of their particular similarities. Both
fascism and neoliberalism are utopian political projects with different ends,
overlapping means and similar causes. The raison d’être of Nazism, for example,
was the colonization of Eastern Europe, the internal purge of Jews,
homosexuals, the disabled, and other “undesirables,” and the defeat of communism
and the left writ large. All of the parties committed to establishing and
maintaining the regime were extremely excited at the prospect of the first and
the third of these goals, and at least indifferent (but frankly often
enthusiastic) about the second. Colonization would be good for business,
restorative to the military, and provide Hitler his much-desired Lebensraum for
“racial health” and prosperity of the Aryan-German people.
The raison
d’être of neoliberalism, however, is to extend market relations and principles
to every facet of society, from “the economy” itself to the state all the way
down to redefining basic understandings of the human being. Citizens become
consumers; humanity becomes “human capital,” people become amorphous,
reinventing, endlessly flexible, resilient, risk-taking individuals. Even
beyond the human, there are cellular processes, algorithms, and chemical
compounds rife for market optimization. Neoliberalism — far more than 1930s-era
fascism (although this does appear to be changing with the new and alt-right) —
is also a transnational and evangelical project. Instead of only the reliance
on brute force that characterized fascist expansion in both its plans and
practice, neoliberalism also employs interlocking international regulatory,
banking, and trade organizations.
Neoliberalism (a term nowadays nearly always
disavowed) is confusingly nested in layered combinations of treaty obligations,
memberships, and, above all, the private power of capital and finance — as in
the European Union. Despite its propaganda, it doesn’t actually seek state
annihilation or even the formal end of parliamentary procedure that we saw in
Nazism. Rather, it captures and transforms the state, such that its sovereignty
is reduced and its power rescinded in some areas (for example, in the
retraction of business and finance regulation, even in its ability to collect
taxes), but radically expanded in others, regulating labor organization,
setting up particular patent processes that can only be maneuvered by a few key
corporations, requiring citizens to partake in private economic activity, and
even, as a much more basic level, the ever-increasing direct and restrictive
governance of the individual. This can range from the pushes and nudges of
taxes, tax incentives, restrictive “zones” for, say, “free speech” whether
political protest or religious observance, to the domination at the daily level
by the police with a seeming free hand especially over specific subject
populations.
There are
numerous, stark differences, to say the least. Nazism is unimaginable without
the ideological commitment and technical capacity for racial elimination. In
contrast, neoliberalism prefers a kind of constrained, elite cosmopolitanism
with racialized power — critical for internal policing and for intervention in
non-neoliberal states — portrayed as incidental, a sideshow. Put in slightly
different terms, neoliberalism would never really want to “solve” the “Jewish
Question.” Neoliberalism constrains national sovereignty in the direction of
transnational “free trade” (favored trade for concentrated capital). Nazism and
fascism pushed for a kind of export-driven autarky. Nazism gave capitalism a
partially reluctant embrace — as a kindred, social Darwinian worldview, a kind
of continuation of national tradition and order, and a necessary means for the
renewal of the German economy in general, and for the rearmament of the nation.
In contrast, neoliberalism — consolidated at least intellectually in the
immediate postwar era — explicitly seeks the extension and protection of
capitalism at all costs.
The Crisis
of Democracy
The key to
the political economies of these regimes is the question of democracy. One need
not be particularly radical to recognize the fundamental contradiction between
democracy and capitalism, or put different between democracy and economic
liberalism. As far back as Aristotle it was always the assumption that
democratic polities would be ones inclined to redistribute goods. It only made
sense: if power is truly distributed on a broad basis even approaching equality
then surely communities would choose to at least exercise democratic control
over “property” if not to just democratize it all straight away. Both fascists
and neoliberals — born out of crises in capital demanding a political response
— have different answers to the modern version of this classical dilemma.
In a
meeting with German business leaders in 1933, Hitler declared that “democracy”
(i.e., actual parliamentary control) was fundamentally incompatible with a
free-market capitalist economy, a truth far more widely acknowledged in that
era. Following Hitler’s speech, Göring presented the Nazi case in blunt terms:
support the Nazi party and parliamentary democracy would end. The threat to
free enterprise from communism, socialism, organized labor, and even basic
formal democracy would be over. Göring concluded: “the sacrifices asked for […]
would be so much easier for industry to bear if it realized that the election
of March 5th will surely be the last one for the next 10 years, probably even
for the next 100 years.” These “sacrifices” were the millions of Deutsche marks
that Schacht proceeded to collect from the room.
This does
not mean that fascism was completely “un-democratic” either. Hitler, Mussolini,
and Franco all based the legitimacy of their rule on fundamentally “democratic”
principles. They claimed to represent the “true” vox populi, the spirit of the
Volk, the will of the nation. Thus, far more interesting than its electoral
crawl to building a minority coalition government, the democracy of fascism is
better reflected in its attempts to mobilize the population and involve
German-Aryans in raising their voices through mass actions, demonstrations, and
affinity groups.
In
contrast, neoliberalism’s prime reaction to the contradiction between democracy
and capitalism has been to reshape and redeploy government functions and
services through “marketization” and hybridizing, and to refashion the entire
concept of politics itself as yet another market. Indeed, by neoliberal
standards, non-participation can (and is) often argued to be perfectly
“rational” in a kind of homo-economicus argument pushed ad infinitum. Reducing
“democracy” to its most transactional structure — votes exchanged for services
rendered, the formal motions of a liberal republican state for at least a
plurality of citizens — neoliberalism achieves a feat that the great
revolutionary and reactionary movements of the 19th and 20th century never
achieved: unique among critiques of parliamentarianism, neoliberalism
discourages participation without undermining legitimacy.
One of the
key differences between neoliberalism and fascism is that, more and more
neoliberalism relies not on a claim to democratic legitimacy but on a kind of
“naturalism”; “there is no alternative,” Margaret Thatcher famously quipped.
This is a seismic shift. For nearly the whole of political modernity, some form
of democracy — whether in the shape of formal mechanisms, nationalist identity,
or egalitarian ideals — had defined the range of political legitimacy, right or
left, authoritarian or anarchistic. Pro-forma liberal rites are held onto as
the tepid nod to democratic legitimacy when the truth of the matter is that
neoliberalism doesn’t want participation or democracy of any kind. It doesn’t
want youth wings or national mobilizations (even for its many wars), but rather
would maintain its citizens and workforce in a state of insecurity and anxiety.
Either it has better use for your time (maximum productivity) or no use for you
at all (except as an economically helpful surplus population, perhaps best
controlled through racialized mass incarceration). Just as with the Nazi
decimation of the formal state, the neoliberal “restructuring” of the state
requires the large scale, expansive and expensive rule of supermanagers. The
dismantling of democratic oversight and control, for example, although often
framed as “efficiency,” inevitably creates either more bureaucracy or more
arcane structures.
Relieved of
the burden of democracy, and born of a clearer purpose, the Supermanagerial
Reich would seem a contender to last a thousand years were it not for its own
endemic crises —particularly financial instability and ecological catastrophe.
Nazism responded to the worldwide financial crisis and the aftermath of World
War I by promising prosperity and dignity through national unity. Neoliberalism
grew from the “supply shock” (i.e., oil crisis) and capital strike of the 1970s
(the ecological crisis may prove to be the quicker catastrophe for neoliberal
rule depending on political outcomes; a prospect that absolutely no one should
celebrate). In fact, although neoliberalism draws on intellectual tools
developed going all the way back to the end of the World War II, it can be
helpful to think of it as an extension of the power of that capital strike into
its own form of society. If colonization and eradication were the promises that
Nazism would not break — even to its dying minutes — a devotion to solutions
found only in the market is the line that neoliberalism cannot cross. Its
intellectual and institutional structures are built precisely to prevent the
kind of widespread prosperity that was seen by the late ’60s, near full
employment in particular.
Neoliberalism
has now clearly outlasted the 2008 financial crisis, and further consolidated
and entrenched both its forms of governance and the concentration of wealth and
income for the top 0.1 percent. But chinks in the armor of the new
Supermanagerial Reich are visible. One of the biggest is the rise of neofascism
nearly the world over, with its promises of economic and ethno-nationalism to
deliver prosperity, or at the very least representation. To deliver, in other
words, what neoliberalism never could.
In 1939,
Max Horkheimer famously wrote, “whoever is not prepared to talk about
capitalism should also remain silent about fascism.” As a recent Jewish Marxist
refugee from Germany, he was in a better position than most to opine on the
dangers of fascism. We argue that this dictum still holds, while it perhaps
needs a 21st-century update. Anyone who takes seriously the threat of the newly
empowered reactionary right, must take seriously the role neoliberalism has
played in laying out the red carpet for its arrival. Instead of handwringing
over liberal dead letters, we must come to terms with the fact that we have
already been living in a form of deeply destructive authoritarian liberalism
for nearly four decades now.
While there
is much gnashing of teeth over our own, cartoonish Hitler wannabe, too many
political actors seem more than willing to turn their heads away from our own
Supermanagerial Reich. Like mid-1930s Germans, too many are quite simply
comfortable with the rolling slow-motion horror that has been neoliberalism.
They view the Trumps and the Le Pens and the Erdoğans, and so forth as a new
crisis, a sudden shock to the system. Many in the United States fear a Trump election
because there might be an explosion of state repression against the vulnerable,
particularly against specific racial and ethnic minorities. And yet, the
neoliberal state has already created a penal system to rival the world’s most
authoritarian dictatorships. The United States imprisons more citizens (total
and per capita) than any other country on Earth, and African Americans and
Latinos at a vastly over-represented rate. Many fear Trump would bring massive
deportations of undocumented immigrants. And yet, the neoliberal state already
engages in mass deportations, at the level of millions during the current
administration, with countless more waiting in dire conditions in the world’s
largest network of immigrant detention camps. Many fear a Trump election would
bring mass persecution, surveillance, and restrictions for American Muslims.
And yet, the neoliberal state already spies on Muslims, administers religious
tests at borders, and polices Muslims for nothing more than their religious
practices. Many fear a Trump election might bring economic ruin, and yet, for
most Americans, wealth is vanishing, wages stagnant, real unemployment steady.
While their
economic nationalisms are doomed and their ethno-nationalisms are abhorrent,
the Trumps, Le Pens, and Farages are correct that the “established order” is
not delivering for the vast majority of people. Furthermore, people do not
simply feel more and more disenfranchised, they quite simply are. Trump would
probably bring an erratic, unpredictable foreign policy. And yet, all that the
neoliberal state has delivered in this arena are unending wars of aggression,
intervention, and destabilization for political and economic gain. Many call
Trump a fascist. Yet it is the crime of wars of aggression that is considered
the principle or greatest charge in the Nuremberg Charter, the crime which sets
the stage for “war crimes” and “crimes against humanity.” If there is going to
be a politics that overcomes the new fascist threat, it must address the fact
that the crisis is not now, the crisis has already been for some time. By
focusing only on the threat of our homegrown Hitler caricature we have failed
to notice the facts right in front of our faces: the uniquely parallel
structures, the same winners, the similar losers, the crimes, the human
degradation. We are already living in our very own, cruel 21st-century
Supermanagerial Reich.
The
Supermanagerial Reich. By Ajay Singh Chaudhary, Raphaële Chappe. Los Angeles Review of Books, November 7, 2016
No comments:
Post a Comment