The Enlightenment is
having a renaissance, of sorts. A handful of centrist and conservative writers
have reclaimed the 17th- and 18th-century intellectual movement as a response
to nationalism and ethnic prejudice on the right and relativism and “identity
politics” on the left. Among them are Jordan Peterson, the Canadian
psychologist who sees himself as a bulwark against the forces of “chaos” and
“postmodernism”; Steven Pinker, the Harvard cognitive psychologist who argues,
in Enlightenment Now, for optimism and human progress against those “who
despise the Enlightenment ideals of reason, science, humanism, and progress”;
and conservative pundit Jonah Goldberg, who, in Suicide of the West, argues in
defense of capitalism and Enlightenment liberalism, twin forces he calls “the
Miracle” for creating Western prosperity.
In their telling, the
Enlightenment is a straightforward story of progress, with major currents like
race and colonialism cast aside, if they are acknowledged at all. Divorced from
its cultural and historical context, this “Enlightenment” acts as an
ideological talisman, less to do with contesting ideas or understanding
history, and more to do with identity. It’s a standard, meant to distinguish
its holders for their commitment to “rationalism” and “classical liberalism.”
But even as they
venerate the Enlightenment, these writers actually underestimate its influence
on the modern world. At its heart, the movement contained a paradox: Ideas of
human freedom and individual rights took root in nations that held other human
beings in bondage and were then in the process of exterminating native
populations. Colonial domination and expropriation marched hand in hand with
the spread of “liberty,” and liberalism arose alongside our modern notions of
race and racism.
These weren’t incidental
developments or the mere remnants of earlier prejudice. Race as we understand
it—a biological taxonomy that turns physical difference into relations of
domination—is a product of the Enlightenment. Racism as we understand it now,
as a socio-political order based on the permanent hierarchy of particular
groups, developed as an attempt to resolve the fundamental contradiction
between professing liberty and upholding slavery. Those who claim the
Enlightenment’s mantle now should grapple with that legacy and what it means
for our understanding of the modern world.
To say that “race” and “racism”
are products of the Enlightenment is not to say that humans never held slaves
or otherwise classified each other prior to the 18th century. Recent
scholarship shows how proto- and early forms of modern race thinking (you could
call them racialism) existed in medieval Europe, with near-modern forms taking
shape in the 15th and 16th centuries. In Spain, for example, we see the turn
from anti-Judaism to anti-Semitism, where Jewish ancestry itself was grounds
for suspicion, versus Jewish practice. And as historian George Fredrickson
notes in Racism: A Short History, “the prejudice and discrimination directed at
the Irish on one side of Europe and certain Slavic peoples on the other
foreshadowed the dichotomy between civilization and savagery that would characterize
imperial expansion beyond the European continent.” One can find nascent forms
of all of these ideas in antiquity—indeed, early modern thinkers drew from all
of these sources to build our notion of race.
But it took the
scientific thought of the Enlightenment to create an enduring racial taxonomy
and the “color-coded, white-over-black” ideology with which we are familiar.
This project, undertaken by the leading thinkers of the time, involved “the
setting aside of the metaphysical and theological scheme of things for a more
logical description and classification that ordered humankind in terms of
physiological and mental criteria based on observable ‘facts’ and tested
evidence,” as historian Ivan Hannaford wrote in Race: The History of an Idea in
the West.
Johann Friedrich
Blumenbach’s influential 1776 volume On the Natural Varieties of Mankind
posited five divisions of humanity, beginning with “Caucasians.” These
frameworks evolved into theories of racial difference, developed to square a
conceptual circle. If natural rights are universal—if everyone has the capacity
to reason—then what is the explanation for enslaved Africans or “savages” in
the Americas, who do not seem to act and reason like white Europeans? The
answer is biological inferiority, in accordance with those racial
classifications.
Immanuel Kant sketched
out a more formalized racial hierarchy in his own anthropological work. “In the
hot countries the human being matures earlier in all ways but does not reach
the perfection of the temperate zones,” Kant wrote. “Humanity exists in its
greatest perfection in the white race … The yellow Indians have a smaller
amount of Talent. The Negroes are lower and the lowest are a part of the
American peoples.” Elsewhere, Kant asserted that “[Whites] contain all the
impulses of nature in affects and passions, all talents, all dispositions to
culture and civilization and can as readily obey as govern. They are the only
ones who always advance to perfection.” This racial theorizing can’t simply be
divorced from the moral philosophy for which he’s hailed, since, as the late
Emmanuel Eze has noted, it comprised a substantial portion of Kant’s career.
Eze writes in “The Color of Reason: The Idea of ‘Race’ in Kant’s Anthropology”:
Kant’s position on the importance of skin
color not only as encoding but as proof of this codification of rational
superiority or inferiority is evident in a comment he made on the subject of
the reasoning capacity of a “black” person. When he evaluated a statement made
by an African, Kant dismissed the statement with the comment: “this fellow was
quite black from head to foot, a clear proof that what he said was stupid.” It
cannot, therefore, be argued that skin color for Kant was merely a physical
characteristic. It is, rather, evidence of an unchanging and unchangeable moral
quality
Eze’s re-examination in
the 1990s kicked off a flood of research and dialogue—some critical, some
supportive. Either way, it is fair to say that Kant’s race theorizing matters
for how we understand the history of race. On this point, philosopher Robert
Bernasconi is blunt: “[Kant] supplied the first scientific definition of race;
he promoted this definition when it was challenged, and he saw it adopted by
some of the leading students of human varieties at that time.”
John Locke precedes
Kant, but his work also shows the influence of early modern racial thinking. In
“The Contradictions of Racism: Locke, Slavery, and the Two Treatises,”
Bernasconi and Anika Maaza Mann present the pre-eminent liberal philosopher as
an architect of the race-based slavery developing in the American colonies
during the mid–17th century. At a time when religious conversion could spare an
African or Native American from permanent servitude, Locke wrote a provision in
The Fundamental Constitutions of Carolina—the governing document for the colony
that would become North Carolina and South Carolina—that specified that slaves
could be “of what opinion or Religion soever … But yet, no Slave shall hereby
be exempted from that civil dominion his Master has over him, but be in all
other things in the same State and condition he was in before.” About the same
time, when there was still widespread debate over the treatment of enslaved
people, Locke changed a clause in that constitution to give slave owners
“absolute power and Authority” (versus “absolute Authority”) over their slaves,
giving them full rein to treat slaves as they pleased.
It is true that, in his
Two Treatises on Government, Locke proclaimed himself an opponent of “slavery.”
But this “slavery” refers to the political domination of an absolute monarch.
In the second of the treatises, Locke provides a justification for slavery as a
result of war, using the same “absolute power” language that grants slave
owners the power of life and death over their slaves. While his argument
doesn’t fit the hereditary chattel slavery taking shape in the Americans, it
was nonetheless used to justify the practice. For Bernasconi and Mann, the
Locke of the Two Treatises must be read in dialogue with the Locke of the The
Fundamental Constitutions, and can’t be bracketed from his role as a colonial
administrator and investor in the slave trade. This Locke, they argue, must be
understood as concerned mainly “with the freedom and prosperity of Englishmen,
and not troubled if they were gained at the expense of Africans.”
One can make a similar
argument with regard to Native Americans. In Liberalism: A Counter-History,
Domenico Losurdo notes how “the Second Treatise makes repeated reference to the
‘wild Indian,’ who moved around ‘insolent and injurious in the woods of
America’ or the ‘vacant places of America.’ ” For Locke, “God gave the world to
men in common; but since he gave it them for their benefit and for the greatest
conveniences of life they could get from it, he can’t have meant it always to
remain common and uncultivated.” In the context of English settlement, it’s an
argument for theft.
It should be said that
this view is contested. Recent scholarship challenges this vision of
Locke—situating him in a broader conversation that leaves him less tolerant of
slavery than he appears. Still, as one of the widely read thinkers of the
period, his work remained influential to slaveholders, including the author of
the Declaration of Independence, Thomas Jefferson, and the Framers of the
Constitution, for whom racial slavery and native expropriation were compatible
with natural rights and representative government. Decades later, South
Carolina’s John C. Calhoun would appeal to Locke in his defense of individual
liberties and attacks on “absolute governments” that turn “the governed” into
“the slaves of the rulers.” Calhoun’s cause, of course, was slavery.
For modern-day
philosopher Charles Mills, this joint march of liberalism and white
supremacy—whether Locke’s social contract or Kant’s moral theory—supports the
notion of an implicit “racial contract” undergirding the Enlightenment project.
“[T]he Racial Contract establishes a racial polity, a racial state, and a
racial juridical system, where the status of whites and nonwhites is clearly
demarcated, whether by law or custom. And the purpose of this state … is
specifically to maintain and reproduce this racial order, securing the
privileges and advantages of the full white citizens and maintaining the
subordination of nonwhites.” As European powers spread across the globe, they
used racial notions of personhood—pioneered by Enlightenment thinkers—to
justify brutality and domination as the march of “civilization.”
This paradox between
Enlightenment liberalism and racial domination was well-recognized from the
beginning. “You Americans make a great Clamour upon every little imaginary
infringement of what you take to be your Liberties; and yet there are no People
upon Earth such Enemies to Liberty, such absolute Tyrants, where you have the
Opportunity, as you yourselves are,” jeered one English interlocutor to
Benjamin Franklin in 1764. Responding to the first American Continental
Congress in 1774, Samuel Johnson replied to “no taxation without
representation” with, “How is it we hear the loudest yelps for liberty from the
drivers of negroes?” Criticizing England’s role in the slave trade in 1776,
Josiah Tucker wrote that “We … the boasted Patrons of Liberty, and the
professed Advocates for the natural Rights of Mankind, engage deeper in this
murderous inhuman Traffic than any Nation whatever.” Writers of African
ancestry at the time, like Baron de Vastey of Haiti, made note of the hypocrisy
of Enlightenment philosophers. Arguably, the only Enlightenment revolution to
do justice to its universal aspirations was the Haitian Revolution, whose
authors—like Toussaint L’Ouverture—appealed to those values as they fought
slavery and colonialism to establish self-governance.
Today’s popular
discourse on the Enlightenment ignores this contradiction and its modern
manifestations, seen in the persistence of race hierarchy in the world’s oldest
democracy. Some self-proclaimed defenders of Enlightenment ideals have even
gone so far as to ridicule the idea of a connection between the Enlightenment
and our modern ideas of race and racial hierarchy, as if the scholarship didn’t
exist. This isn’t just unfortunate, it’s ironic—a betrayal of the higher
principles of the Enlightenment, of the commitment to evidence, observation,
reason, and deliberation. It’s also dangerous.
We still live in a world
shaped by Enlightenment ideas of race and white supremacy. These notions of
inherent inferiority still hold purchase in our society. And political
liberalism is still too compatible with both. The path to a truly universal
liberalism—one that can actually liberate—demands that we grapple with its ugly
heritage. To confront the paradox of the Enlightenment is to take its values
seriously; to dismiss it is to prefer hagiography to truth.
By Jamelle Bouie. Slate , June 5, 2018.
No comments:
Post a Comment