In his
articles, lectures, and books, Hong Kong-based philosopher Yuk Hui shows how
the philosophy of technology, once seen as a narrow and specialised field,
opens an enormous, almost all-encompassing, range of topics. In a time marked
by dystopian determinism – often cast in variants of transhumanist ideology –
Hui calls for a fragmentation of the future in which a multitude of deeply
different developments can cross-pollinate: His goal is to help understand and
nourish the kind of dynamic openness that tends to get lost in a globalised
technological monoculture. Going beyond the mere proliferation of technological
gadgets and systems, such diversity involves rediscovering forgotten techniques
as well as new ways of dealing with technology based on different purposes and
ways of experiencing the world.
Hui’s
work draws on both Eastern and Western philosophy, especially twentieth-century
philosophers known for their thoughts on technology like Martin Heidegger,
Gilbert Simondon, and Bernard Stiegler, as well as his early training as a
computer engineer. Recently, his writing has increasingly taken on geopolitical
issues. Technology unites the world, but it is also a topic well suited to
discuss differences. In The Question Concerning Technology in China (2016), he
made East Asia a testing ground for his concepts of technodiversity and
cosmotechnics, which are pivotal to his technological approach to cultural
difference. In his latest book, Art and Cosmotechnics (2021),Hui expands this
project to involve artistic and aesthetic thought. Moving beyond the
established premise that new technologies transform artistic practices, Hui
envisions another process: transforming technology through art. As he excavates
the roots of our cultural history in order to probe the future, he shows us
how, in the multifarious landscape of thought, art, and technology, a deeper
transformation needs to be brought forth. If our desire to calculate everything
has only succeeded in making the end predictable, then in order to regain the
future we must nurture our relationship to the unknown.
AD : Art
and Cosmotechnics, is a work about aesthetics, but the underlying premise comes
not so much from art, but from the deepest interconnections between technology,
philosophy, and geopolitics. The appeal of this combination is a strong sense
that the future as such is at stake in thinking.
YH : My
point of departure is that we are living in the epoch of technology, but also
that technology today constitutes an enormous metaphysical force that pushes us
to an unknown destination which we are now more and more collectively
experiencing as something catastrophic, for example, aggravating climate change,
intensive competition of military technologies, and so on.
AD : Yet
every country on the planet strives for technological progress and the many new
possibilities it offers, not least in Asia. Our desires for tangible
improvements prove stronger than our somewhat vague fears or worries over
technology. In pre-modern times, the old traditions were systematically valued
higher than the new. How did we begin to value the new over the old?
YH : Even
if they are everywhere today, it is fair to say that modern technologies
originate from Western thought. In the West, modern sciences were applied to
technology at the beginning of the industrial revolution, until technoscience
began to operate autonomously later on, changing everybody’s lives and becoming
a planetary phenomenon. While it is true that technoscience and
industrialisation created ruptures throughout Europe in modern times, there was
still a certain continuity and a gradual development. This was not the
experience in China and Japan, where the technological acceleration has been so
much faster. In Asia you find a strong fascination with the modern, which still
can be felt today, where technology really is an object of desire.
AD : On
the other hand, you have the geopolitical competition which you describe in The
Question Concerning Technology in China. Even if fascination and desire help
usher in modernisation, you point out that the deeper sources of the rapid
change we see in Asia is historically Japan’s competition with the West and
China’s efforts to supersede the West after the historical humiliation of the
Opium Wars. The revolutionary changes transform everyday life and the social
geography, but you explore the deeper cultural effects, a break with the past
so drastic that it sometimes is experienced as a cultural breakdown. How does
this affect philosophy?
YH : The
modernisation we have seen in China, in Japan, in India, and which is now
happening in Africa, has completely transformed the landscape of thinking. You
could say that it has changed the sensibility towards what is new and what is
normal, but also that it makes traditional thought irrelevant. Today, when one
asks how you apply the ancient moral philosophy of Confucianism to the question
of sex robots, for instance, it might sound ridiculous, not only because they
are from two different epochs, but also because firstly, the philosophical
tradition didn’t treat technology thematically, and secondly, the technologies
it has conceived were so different from Western technologies, epistemologically
and ontologically. So, there is an incompatibility between the old and the new,
between traditional thought and modern technologies, just as between Eastern
and Western modes of thought. But instead of seeing it as an “unhappy
consciousness,” I consider this incompatibility as precisely what can give rise
to new possibilities: to transform our technologies, our thinking, and our
thinking about technology.
AD : The
unhappy consciousness, as Hegel saw it, is a kind of powerless criticism where
the freedom of thought, which senses that things could be otherwise,
nonetheless comes up against what seems to be unbending realities. To get out
of such an impasse, you often bring up the need for what you call
“technodiversity.” With the call for diversity you seem to imply that for all
the varieties of gadgets and systems, we suffer under a technological
monoculture – not just in technologies that are globally ubiquitous and
interconnected, but in a certain mindset that underpins them.
YH : Exactly,
ever since the modern technological developments began in the 18th century and
the industrial revolution, the logic of technology hasn’t changed very much. It
revolves around what we – with Weber, Marcuse, or Habermas – would call
rationalisation, which involves a calculative and instrumental use of reason to
control the surroundings; it is a form of domination. That also resonates with
Heidegger’s understanding of modern technology. He drew up a distinction
between the ancient Greek techne and modern technology, whose essence he named
gestell– meaning that everything is regarded as a resource, or standing
reserve, to be exploited. It is also in modern technology that Heidegger sees
the end or completion of Western philosophy or Western metaphysics. This end comes
about as thinking increasingly becomes a matter of calculation, while at the
same time the technoscience which originally sprung forth in Europe becomes
planetarised.
AD : In
Art and Cosmotechnics, you devote much more attention to the ancient Greeks and
to Taoism in the East than to discussions on contemporary art, artificial
intelligence, and high-tech. This is perhaps not what people immediately expect
when they hear talk about the relationship between art and technology, since in
most people’s minds “technology” is squarely identified with new technologies,
instruments, and systems.
YH : Today,
in almost every university around the world, people want to work on arts and
technology, and it happens in departments of engineering just as much as in art
schools. Lots of funding is channeled into the emerging new fields of art and
technology, exploring things like virtual reality and artificial intelligence.
In Asia, in particular, we have seen lot of discourse on arts and technology.
Some decades ago, in Europe, we saw what is called new media arts – and the
interest in new technologies has been going on intensely for decades. Yet it
seems to me that the relation between art and technology is not yet determined.
We could
perhaps say that there are two dominant ways of thinking here. The first simply
regards technology as a tool and adopts new technologies to do art, such as
what we see now with virtual reality, augmented reality, Metaverse, etc. This
is the common perspective on art and technology, even for laymen. For artists,
new technologies provide new ways of making art more interactive and more means
to access the art market, for example the current hype of NFTs (non-fungible
tokens).
AD : These
NFTs not only use blockchain to guarantee the authenticity of artworks, but can
also make buyers shareholders in a work of art, attempting to create
communities of shared ownership to empower the artist. At the same time, the
speculative side of art is encouraged even further. Adopting a new technology
is more than just using a new tool, since the tool tends to radically change
the nature of what you are doing.
YH : Such
observations give rise to a second approach, which we find exemplified already
in Benjamin’s essay The Work of Art in the Age of Technological Reproducibility
[1935]. Whereas his colleagues Horkheimer and Adorno worried about art becoming
an industrial product – something commercial, seductive, and shallow, cultural
commodities for deceiving the mass – Benjamin tried to say something very different.
Instead of questioning whether photography or film is art, he suggested asking
how photography and cinema transform the concept of art itself. From this
materialist point of view, the concept of art has to be renewed constantly. I
would say that these two views, technology as an artistic instrument and as a
materialist power transforming art, dominate in the common as well as the
intellectual understanding of art and technology today. Benjamin’s great text
once had a revolutionary potential, since it rejects existing categorisations
of art, but now it might have become dogmatic in a way. Maybe it is time we
turn the question around. What if we don’t just ask how technology transforms
the concept of art, but instead try to do the opposite and ask how art can
transform technology? I want to make this question a turning point, to see if
it will allow us to peek into a new field of possibilities, to readdress the
relationship between art, technology, and thinking.
AD ; Does
this mean reviving through technology the utopian potential of art that the
avant-garde was hoping for: a transformation of our world in a time when it is
increasingly dominated by our technologies?
YH : Yes,
I think this is precisely how I have been trying to rethink the avant-garde. Technology
and art have tended to be seen as separate, but now with the great emphasis on
technology and art, and all the energy and talent that go into it, there might
be a possibility to make some changes. Otherwise, we’ll just keep on pursuing
what is new while following the same logic.
AD : In
exploring the relation between art and technology in the East, you go back to
some of the most traditional art forms. How can these ancient traditions be
brought to life and really make a difference in a modern world?
YH : In
the context of East Asia, there have been a lot of efforts to preserve
traditional thinking, not just in the philosophy departments, but also, for
example, through the popularisation of Chinese classics and so forth. Such
preservation is not oriented towards the future, but the past. It is the same
in the arts, where there is a lot of emphasis on traditional craftsmanship,
also.
AD : Such
efforts at reintegrating tradition was also central to the Arts and Crafts
movement in Europe – as well as in regional schools of design today.
YH : Similarly,
in China today, we have seen a revival of Shanshui painting. The name literally
means “mountain and water,” which is the term for traditional Chinese landscape
painting. Historically, one way of modernising tradition would be to try to
absorb the Western art of the 20th century. Academies sent people to Paris and
Berlin to learn painting and tried to integrate realist painting in Chinese
traditions. It contributed to the creation of styles and exchange of skills,
but not much beyond. In the revival of Shanshui painting today, there is also a
desire to live in the mountain and water environment in retreats, seeking a
kind of zen spirituality, but this opportunity is often only available to the
ultra-rich or burnt-out nihilists. In an effort to integrate technologies,
there have even been international competitions to design Shanshui cities –
mountain and water urban projects.
AD : Are
you implying that all these attempts at integrating past and future, the East
and West, remain too superficial?
YH ; Their
failure testifies to an unelaborated incompatibility. But if traditions are
incompatible with modern technologies and modern life, this incompatibility can
also generate new thought. The question is how to elaborate it. In China,
Shanshui painting was an intellectual art, just as tragedy in the West was
always considered intellectual. Ever since Baumgarten declared aesthetics a
kind of cognition, but of an inferior kind, it would never be seen as something
as clear and distinct as logic; Leibniz famously termed this
un-conceptualisable experience “je ne sais quoi.” We can also take note of the
fact that Kant defined the beautiful negatively, as purposiveness without
purpose, as pleasure without interest. One thing I tried to do in Art and
Cosmotechnics is to elevate aesthetics to logic, or, more precisely, recursive
logic – the continuation of my previous work Recursivity and Contingency
[2019]. For example, in the philosophy of tragedy, a distinct tragic logic has
been developed after Aristotle in the West by Schelling, Hegel, and others. For
this tradition, I employ the concept tragist. In the same vein, I am searching
for a logic of Shanshui painting, or a Daoist logic. Shanshui landscape
painting builds on oppositions, like that which falls and that which rises, the
visible and the invisible, but they are oppositions which are at the same time
continuous and in harmony.
AD : It is
also interesting that you point out how Chinese art seeks to evade the strong
emotions and sad passions of tragedy, giving a preference to harmony, and to
“blandness,” as the French sinologist and philosopher François Jullien has
emphasised in his book In Praise of Blandness (1991/2007).
YH : During
a symposium in London in 2016, I had a panel discussion with François Jullien.
We were asked why there is nothing resembling tragedy in China. Jullien
answered that it is because the Chinese have developed a thinking (pensée) to
avoid tragedy. The problem with this statement, interesting as it may be, is
that the Chinese can hardly try to avoid tragedy, since they didn’t know what
it was. The fact is that Chinese culture was no soil to Greek tragedy; this has
been discussed by authors such as Jean-Pierre Vernant and George Steiner, among
many others.
Some
people would misread Jullien’s response and see him as culturalist, or even an
orientalist, ascribing an essential mentality to certain regions or peoples.
Even my own books have been misread this way, when people refuse to read the
book and judge from the title. The fact is that when I speak of Chinese
thought, I am trying to find out how one can start out from a locality and, by
identifying the incompatibilities, to help a new thinking emerge. This is what
I term the individuation of thinking in Art and Cosmotechnics.
AD : How
should we understand what you call individuation here?
YH : I
use this term in the sense of Gilbert Simondon. He saw it as a process of
formation, which can take place even in lifeless nature as in crystals, and
evidently there is individuation when a plant or animal takes shape, as well as
in the development of psychological humans or social structures. If we look at
Simondon’s example of crystals of sodium chloride, that is salt, they take
shape in a saturated solution in water. Before this happens there is a moment
of instability with a lot of tension, with incompatibilities between positive
and negative ions. Then [the solution] reaches a threshold – for instance, if
you heat it up – where crystallisation begins. We see a restructuration where
crystals germinate and spread, where information is distributed, until the
solution has fully crystallised. Simondon insists that this model of tension,
threshold, and restructuration can be applied also to living beings, to
psychological and social processes. My idea is that the differences or
incompatibilities between the old and the new, the tensions between the East
and the West, could be appropriated from a height which allows individuation to
take place, and also a new vision for art and technology. Indeed, for myself,
it is inevitable to be a tragist Daoist or a Daoist tragist.
AD : So,
we have to think of a plethora of technologies and arts, each with different
roots and corresponding traditions of thought and interpretation, while
maintaining that they can be compared as different approaches to the same, or
at least similar enough to be brought into a fruitful dialogue?
YH : There
are of course millions of technologies in the world, and if you set out to
describe them and their differences you become a sociologist or an
anthropologist. That is why the philosopher searches for something more
essential, like Martin Heidegger claimed at the beginning of his essay The
Question Concerning Technology [1954]. In Heidegger’s text on art The Origin of
the Work of Art [1935-37/1950], which was written almost at the same time as
Benjamin’s essay, he emphasises that for the ancient Greeks, both art and
technology are described by the same concept of techne. Art and technology have
another concept in common, namely that of poiesis, bringing forth – a process
which has a certain telos, a goal. To Heidegger, this means that in techne one
experiences the unconcealment of Being. Modern technology, whose essence
Heidegger calls Gestell, still has the possibility of unconcealment, albeit in
the form of what he calls “challenging” [Herausforderung], namely a
confrontation, something overwhelming, even catastrophic. Technology, which is
increasingly about making all thought into a form of calculation ends up
revealing and provoking the incalculable, for example, in the uncanny and
disastrous possibilities like Fukushima and Chernobyl. That is why I see
Heidegger as a tragist.
AD : We
have perhaps regarded technology in this way in the Western world ever since
the Greeks. They dreamed up the origin of fire, the first technology, in the
tragic destiny of the titan Prometheus, who stole it from Zeus and the gods of
Olympus. We seem to always suspect technologies as a transgression, something
dangerous, that gives mastery, but which might also lead to enslavement. Are we
still thinking tragically about technology in the West? And what is the essence
of the tragic here?
YH : We
see ourselves as rebellious, but we also see ourselves as suffering – as
suffering from the fate in which one has no choice. One form of tragist gesture
would be that of Goethe’s Prometheus from his poem written between 1772 and
1774, where he has Prometheus say to Zeus that “you can go away as you like,
the earth will still go on,” because Prometheus has created humans in his own
image. In the tragic world, you cannot stop in front of contradictions, but
must rather take your destiny upon yourself; the essential tragic gesture is to
go all the way.
AD : That
notion is interesting because this is exactly the rhetoric of the new
Prometheans – the transhumanists and ecomodernists in California. New
technological possibilities have to be explored and implemented because it is
our destiny to always advance further, irrespective of the direction. When
climate change sets in because of our domination of earth, we need to dominate
it even more, use more technology to control the climate and the weather. In
one of your essays on technodiversity, you even warn us about the temptation to
cast ourselves as tragic heroes in the fight against environmental disasters –
a position which leads us not only toward hubris, but also to postures of
tragic defeat.
YH : This
rhetoric you mentioned is of course problematic, but it is not tragist; it is
only tragic. That is why I avoid the word tragic and use tragist instead, which
means taking up technologies as necessary things, precisely so that we can
change them. This is what Bernard Stiegler wanted to do in his life – and in
this sense he was a real tragist. For him, it was crucial that we cannot turn
our backs on the knowledge that generated modern technology. Only by seeing it
as necessary can we begin the work of transforming it.
AD : In
your discussions of Taoist or Shanshui logic, you circle around the concept of
the unknown. Can the unknown help us to regain our future as something open, as
it should be – rather than something catastrophic?
It is
clear to me – and this is no longer a question, it is a postulate – that what
Heidegger calls Being is the unknown. The unknown is the incalculable, which is
more than incomputable because the incomputable is a mathematical concept
opposed to the computable, meaning reducible to an algorithm. In Western
philosophy, the unknown is an old topic; it implies immediately the limit of
knowing, going back to Socrates, who says that he “knows that he does not
know.” In Eastern thought, however, the unknown is really fundamental. In my
book, Art and Cosmotechnics, I begin with the words of the Daodejing: “The dao
that can be said is not the eternal dao/ The name that can be named is not the
eternal name.” However, this is not just mystification, just like Wittgenstein
talks about the mystic [das Mystische] without committing to any mystification.
AD : With
him, as perhaps in the Dao-dejing, it had to do with the limits of knowledge,
but also with knowledge about limits, for instance, the limits of language. But
it had little to do with withdrawal to tradition, or irrationalism for that
matter.
YH : For
this reason, I attempted to articulate what I call an epistemology of the
unknown, which is a kind of paradoxical concept because the unknown as such
remains unknowable, so that no epistemology will be applicable. However, one
engages with the unknown even knowing that it is impossible to know it, or one
assumes that one will know it one day. But only through the awareness of its
existence and contradiction is one able to establish a plane of consistency
with the unknown.
AD : For
Deleuze, such a “plane of consistency” is a minimal requirement for thought to
be possible, or for thinking about something at all. How can it help us
approach the unknown, or even the unknowable?
YH : “Undemonstrability”
also conditions the consistency of spiritual life. For example, we cannot
demonstrate the existence of God, but through religious practice and
institutions one is able to create a plane of consistency; one can find in
poetry an extraordinary experience of the unknown, through the unconventional
use of language, the breaking apart of words, and so on.
AD : If
our access to an open and unknown future begins with different potential
futures at a local level, where traditions meet modern technologies, it follows
that the contradictions and incompatibilities are different in each region. You
engage not only with the past and future of China, but also with Latin America,
Russia, and also with Indigenous knowledge. How are your ideas about the local
connected to what you call “planetary thinking?”
YH : In
the very last paragraph of my book on cybernetics, Recursivity and Contingency,
I propose a post-European philosophy. And I should repeat what I said there:
this is a collective task. When Heidegger says that cybernetics – the triumph
of calculation – marks the end of European philosophy, he also means that there
will be a post-European philosophy and this post-European philosophy is called
“thinking.” So, this is also a moment to think about the landscape of thought,
where thinking has always been limited to a region. We are confined in an
eighteenth-century concept of culture and nationality; even the most radical
thinkers unconsciously label their thinking according to nationalities.
I want
to engage with people from different regions to think about this from their perspective
and from their locality, but not nationality. When I say a post-European
thinking, I’m not saying anything against Europe because I believe that Europe
also needs to go beyond this European thinking. A new philosophy for Europe,
even within Europe itself, cannot simply import Taoism or Buddhism, but must
have the courage to confront incompatibility and see how individuation can take
place. This is the first sense of planetary thinking, a thinking based on
diversities, namely biodiversity, noodiversity (i.e. diversity of thought), and
technodiversity.
To think
about the planetary, especially when we talk about that which we found in Hegel
or in Carl Schmitt, it is still very much based on the nation state and the
necessity of enemies. I think it necessary to think with theorists like
Schmitt, but also to think beyond such political realism. If we follow
realpolitik to the end, we are going to end up with catastrophes because
political realism means relentless military and economic competition.
AD : The
term realpolitik was coined by Ludwig von Rochau, a journalist and politician
who wrote about political realism in the aftermath of the failed revolutions of
1848. He was worried about his fellow idealists, revolutionaries, and radicals
who believed that moral arguments and claims of injustice could really change
the political landscape, and felt responsible to remind them that 99 per cent
of all politics was determined by the logic of power. And that if you don’t
have that in mind, you will not succeed with your 1 per cent of moral
persuasion – or an artistic attempt to change people’s sensibilities for that
matter. Against the utility and sheer power of technology, art seems to be a
weak and feeble force. So, the question is: How is art supposed to influence or
change a force of such magnitude?
YH : I
appreciate that you mention realpolitik and the relation between it and my own
project. When realpolitik is put at the front, there are hardly alternatives
available, since even the most basic things for making changes are conditioned
by this same realpolitik. On the other hand, this might also equally mean that
we still don’t think, or we failed to think. I believe this is probably the
reason we still study and teach philosophy today. We should not underestimate
or undermine the power of thinking in a time when the real is so poorly
understood.
Planetary
Thinking : Philosopher Yuk Hui asks how
art can transform technology. By Anders
Dunker. Kunstkritikk , November 19, 2021.
In his
book On the Existence of Digital Objects
(2016), Chinese philosopher Yuk Hui drew on his background as a computer
engineer and programmer to investigate digital entities like computer viruses,
video clips, algorithms, and networks. In the foreword to the book, the French
philosopher Bernard Stiegler described Hui’s thinking as a “generous and open
theoretical milieu for exploration of human experience in connection to the
infosphere.” A distinctive trait of Hui’s philosophy is its combination of
Eastern thought with the European philosophical tradition. In The Question
Concerning Technology in China: An Essay in Cosmotechnics (2016), Hui analyzes
China’s hyper-rapid modernization in light of its long history of technological
development and its relationship to the West. His most recent book, Recursivity
and Contingency (2019), explores cybernetics and its merging of the artificial
and the natural — i.e., machines and organisms. More than mere reflection, the
philosophy of history underlying Hui’s work can be read as a program for
practical change.
After a
video-call with Hui in Hong Kong, where he was teaching aesthetics, I met with
him in Los Angeles, where we continued our conversation on a visit to the
Griffith Observatory, with its fitting double view of metropole and cosmos. In
our discussion, Hui demonstrated his wide range of interests and his singular
capacity to focus on philosophical problems in order either to solve them or to
move beyond them. As the conversation unfolded, we continued over video-call,
this time from Berlin, where Hui now lives and teaches.
¤
ANDERS
DUNKER: In your book about technology in China, you discuss the concept of
“sinofuturism” — a Chinese vision of the future that is distinctively different
from the one we have in the West. At the same time, you point out that China is
becoming more like the West and thus risks cutting ties with its own
traditions. You describe the new relationship between the Occident and the
Orient as a “dis-orientation.” What does this process entail?
YUK HUI:
The Greeks made a distinction between the Occident, which Germans still call
das Abendland, and the Orient. What counts as Occident and Orient has changed
many times. For the Greeks, the Orient was Egypt and Persia, not China and
Japan. Geographical orientation was also a technical issue, because it was only
through novel navigational instruments that the West discovered the globe. From
the 16th century onward, China and Japan found themselves lagging behind the
West in technology and knowledge. As a direct consequence, the empires of the
East were at last forced to open their gates and accept the colonizing powers
of the West. China wasn’t conquered by the writings, values, or ideas of
Europeans, it was conquered by technological discoveries and inventions. If we
look at the history of East Asia (say, Korea, China, and Japan) we see that each
of these countries at some point decided that they wanted to “catch up with the
West.” One of the reasons was warfare — competition and military activities
were closely connected to colonization. In fact, China started modernizing only
after defeat in the opium wars against the British Empire at the end of the
19th century.
AD : Being
defeated often means you have to copy the conquering enemy. Must we accept this
logic when it comes to modernization, no matter how much we want to reject
cultural imperialism and a universal history wherein some countries and regions
are more advanced while others lag behind?
YH : Let
us remember that Oswald Spengler, in Man and Technics (1931), remarks that
Europeans made a major mistake in exporting their technologies to other
countries at the end of the 19th century. In his opinion, Europeans should have
kept their technologies to themselves to make sure they kept their lead. That
Japan vanquished Russia in 1905 was a signal that they might soon have the
power to surpass the West in technological capacity.
AD : For
centuries, Japan resisted direct competition with the West — for instance,
limiting their artilleries to bows and arrows and banning guns for over 200
years to protect traditional samurai sword fighting. Isn’t it striking that
Japan started modernizing only after American warships forced them to open up
for world trade?
YH : The
West needed hundreds of years to modernize. Japan completed the task in record
time, moving from the middle ages to hypermodernity in 150 years. The same goes
for China. Martin Heidegger wrote in the 1940s that only when communism comes
to power in China will technology be “free.” What does he mean by that? Free
means that it can be everywhere — that there is no longer any resistance.
Heidegger talks about a technological planetarization. He says that
civilization as such will be based on Western European thought, since
non-European cultures haven’t managed to resist European technology. There is
little point in writing local history and bolstering up regional traditions if
you don’t know what to do when Google enters the world stage. Typically, you
withdraw and defend your culture against the new technology, or you marginalize
yourself as a subaltern. What has happened in globalization is that Western
cultures have infiltrated other cultures and turned them upside down.
AD : For
a long time, as you point out in your book, China had a higher technological
level than the West. And yet, China’s modernization still followed a Western
blueprint. Did the world lose the opportunity to see an authentically Chinese
modernity?
YH : This
is the big question. It was meticulously examined by the great sinologist and
philosopher of technology Joseph Needham, who was a world-famous biochemist
before he became a sinologist, writing and editing a great work in 26 volumes
called Science and Civilisation in China (1954–2016). The question he asked
was: If we accept that certain sciences were more advanced in China and the
East than in the West before the 16th century, what were the crucial conditions
that stopped China from developing modern technology and science? I have tried
to ask this question in a different way. If we assume instead that China and
Europe moved in two different directions in their scientific development, we
can also avoid saying that one part of the world is ahead of the other.
AD : Still,
the act of resisting technological change means lagging behind, even in our
times. Is there any viable alternative to the planetarization of technology —
what you call a synchronization of the history of technology?
YH : Instead
of a universal history describing one technology with various stages of
development, we can step back for a moment and instead describe technological
development as involving different cosmotechnics. I call this technodiversity.
Here, we must revisit the question of locality, which doesn’t necessarily
entail that we take part in a discussion of ethnic groups and ideologies:
Aryan, German, Russian, or whatever. We must rather think of locality in terms
of systems of knowledge. Michel Foucault called knowledge systems epistemes and
understood them as ways of life — ways of sensing and ordering experience,
producing in turn certain forms of knowledge. Foucault emphasizes different
epistemes in European history and orders them into epochs: Renaissance
knowledge, classical knowledge, and modern knowledge. In his famous article
“What is Enlightenment?” — which he prepared before his death in 1984 — he says
that we also can understand knowledge as a way of thinking and feeling, as a
sensibility.
AD : In
other words, different places and times have their own epistemes. What would it
take for this diversity not to be effaced by the complete synchronization of
cultural development?
YH : First, we must recognize the diversity;
then we must develop it further. Let me give you an example. I grew up in Hong
Kong. My father had a Chinese pharmacy where he sold plants and herbs. Chinese
pharmacists walk mountain paths collecting herbs to be made into medicines.
Making medicine is a complicated procedure: some plants must first be treated,
to extract the poisonous substances they contain, before they can be made
beneficial to human health. Chinese medicine is based on Daoist cosmology, with
Yin, Yang, and five kinds of Qi. If, from a Western perspective, you approach a
Chinese doctor and ask, “Can you please show me your Qi and prove that this
energy exists?” the answer would have to be no. If you can’t prove the
existence of the energy at the base of your practice, how can you say that you
practice a science? Here lies the problem.
But this
doesn’t mean that Chinese medicine isn’t scientific. As an empirical science,
it has functioned for 2,000 years based on a different epistemology. For a long
time in Hong Kong, Chinese medicine has been ranked lower than Western
medicine. If you go to a Chinese doctor, it won’t be covered by your health
insurance because Chinese medicine is seen as unscientific.
AD : Is
this how Western technology establishes itself as universal, by monopolizing
credibility and marginalizing what is different?
YH : Here
we must be careful. I am not aiming to pit the relative against the universal,
or see the particular in contrast to the universal, as philosophy often has done.
I would rather point out that the universal is just one dimension of what is.
You and I are both humans, but we are individual and different humans. In the
same way, technology has some universal traits: from an anthropological
perspective, technology is an extension of the body and an externalization of
memory. But these gestures don’t work in the same way in all cultures. Chinese
writing and the Latin alphabet are both externalizations of memory, but they
are still extremely different. Chinese pictogram has a very different
philosophical foundation compared to Western phonogram.
Derrida
tried to explore this difference in On Grammatology (1967) in terms of a
philosophy of relation versus a philosophy of substance — Leibniz versus Hegel
— but he didn’t carry it further. Writing is a system for both memory and
education of sensibility, and it can also be seen as a technology to preserve
the distinctiveness of our culture. We cannot say which is better than the
other. For the same reason, I don’t claim that Chinese medicine is better, but
that different systems have different merits. If you have cancer, you might
have to remove the tumor immediately, using surgery, because it can spread
aggressively. Afterward, Chinese medicine can help you recover your health and
strength.
AD : Even
granting that technological diversity has its advantages, is simply promoting
diversity enough to combat the impending and fatal ecological disaster that you
think synchronous technological development is causing? Isn’t it also necessary
to change our technologies en bloc on a global scale?
YH : Western
thinking always draws a distinction between good and bad, and seeks to remove
what is deemed bad. We want to implement everywhere only the good side of
technology. Peter Sloterdijk distinguishes between a dangerous “allotechnics”
manipulating nature and a good “homeotechnics” cooperating with it. Bernard
Stiegler says that technology is always both a poison and a cure, and he wants
to separate the good pharmakon from the bad pharmakon. The division between
good and bad is a philosophical gesture that goes back to Plato. He presents
the philosopher as a judge with the task of determining what is good for the
people.
For me,
this is all very problematic. I don’t think we can come to a global agreement
as to what is good and what is bad. Even if we have common problems we are
trying to solve, that doesn’t mean there is a universal solution. There is no
single way to respond to the collapse of ecosystems. We must understand that variation
is a consequence of local adaptation. Biodiversity develops because of climatic
variations, biological niches, and relations between particular plants,
animals, and microorganisms. Something similar should hold for technologies. We
need to explore the problem of the local, but we must be careful, since this is
an extremely sensitive topic these days. Who is concerned with the local today?
Marine Le Pen in France, Alternative für Deutschland in Germany, Aleksandr
Dugin in Russia.
AD : Dugin
is influenced by a reading of Heidegger that tends to see technology as a tool
for the spread of the moral hollowness he sees in liberal Western societies. To
reject what is foreign and romanticize tradition seems an altogether obvious
and dangerous mode of resistance.
YH : Dugin
misinterprets what Heidegger says. Heidegger doesn’t say that we should resist
technology. He says that we mustn’t forget that there is also something else.
This something else is the unconcealment of Being, which is forgotten in modern
technology. Or, more precisely, the unconcealment in modern technology can only
be carried out through a mode of challenging, of violence. With this statement,
Heidegger abruptly ends his argument, but the way I understand him, he doesn’t
call for a resistance to modern technology but rather a transformation of it.
This transformation is at the same time a stepping back and a leap ahead.
If we
want to deepen our understanding of the local, we should perhaps give a fresh
look at the pre-romantic German thinker Herder, as Peter Sloterdijk told me he
aims to do in a forthcoming book. Herder was the origin of German nationalism
with all it entails, because of what he writes about the spirit of the people —
der Volksgeist. In one way, he was the inventor of “the people.” Herder’s ideas
are dangerous, but if you don’t dare confront danger, as Heidegger says, you
end up with catastrophe.
AD : Herder
was worried that everything distinctive and original would be erased through
the course of history, as the exchange between cultures makes them all similar.
He despaired that Europeans were all speaking French, were forgetting their
national customs, and seemed to dislike their own history and traditions. Today
we find the same process all over the world, evidenced not only by the rapid
loss of languages but also by technological unification. Is the world
inevitably becoming more and more homogeneous?
YH : Herder
defends difference: different ways of life, different languages, different
aesthetics. All these differences he sees as irreducible, as something that
can’t and shouldn’t be replaced by something more universal. At the same time,
we need to remember that Herder is not only a thinker of the local also an
early cosmopolitan thinker, maybe even in a more interesting and theoretically
credible way than Kant, whose courses he has attended in Königsberg. We must
have the local as our point of departure, Herder says, but the local doesn’t
need to be exclusive.
AD : So,
we might aim for a universality that is inclusive of diversity? The Chinese
philosopher Zhao Tingyang has suggested that the Chinese concept of tianxia —
“all under heaven” — is precisely such a concept of inclusive universality.
YH : The
problem, as I see it, is that the concept of tianxia is only relevant as long
as “Heaven” exists. And in a Chinese context, Heaven is Cosmos. Tianxia was the
cosmotechnics of the Chinese government, connecting morality and the cosmos,
legitimizing laws and practices (as well as the government itself). The emperor
was called tianzi, the son of Heaven. As such, he had the legitimacy to be at
the center of the political sovereignty, and to govern the people, including
the fringe “barbarians.”
AD : And
what is cosmotechnics, exactly?
YH : For
the Greeks, “cosmos” means an ordered world. At the same time, the concept
points to what lies beyond the Earth. Morality is first and foremost something
that concerns the human realm. Cosmotechnics, as I understand it, is the
unification of the moral order and cosmic order through technical activities.
If we compare Greece and China in ancient times, we discover that they have
very different understandings of the cosmos, and very different conceptions of
morality as well. The arbitration between them also takes place in different
ways, with different technologies. A cosmotechnics of the tianxia type is no
longer possible in a time that no longer has a conception of “Heaven,” as
people did in the past. Like other big nations, China has satellites orbiting
the Earth. The heavens have become a secular place, utilized by humans, and can
no longer play a role as a morally legitimizing power.
AD : In
Recursivity and Contingency, you speak about the need to “recosmicize the
world.” You borrow this term from Augustin Berque, who pointed out that the
modern world no longer has a cosmos, understood as a moral and meaningful
order, and that colonization by the West has robbed other cultures of their
distinctive conceptions of the cosmos. He says that the universe, as it is
described in science, has nothing to do with the classical cosmos, since
scientific explanation has no moral significance whatsoever. Does this mean
that we are faced with the task of recosmicizing not only our world, but the
universe itself? Is the universe, discovered by astronomy, still waiting to be
given a proper moral significance?
YH : When
we think of astrophysics, we see the universe as a thermodynamic system that
inexorably moves toward destruction and heat-death, where stars are nothing but
basic elements in nuclear reactions and where their twinkling has nothing to do
with us. In this sense, it seems absurd to recosmicize the Earth and the
universe; it can’t lead to anything but superficial mysticism and naïveté.
Astrophysics only informs us of certain facts about the universe. It has no
ambitions of telling us how to live. What kind of life should we imagine in
light of recent astrophysical discoveries? Physics has no ambition to answer
these questions.
“Recosmicizing”
doesn’t mean giving some mystique back to the stars and cosmos, or giving
technology a mystical meaning, but rather understanding that we must develop
ways of life that solve the conflict between modern science and tradition,
between technology and mysticism — whether we choose to talk about the Chinese Dao
or Heidegger’s Sein. We must give the non-rational a place in a culture that is
otherwise rational — the way, for example, that poetry gives the unknown a
place in communication through an unconventional and paradoxical use of
language. Art and philosophy can’t choose science as their point of departure.
If they do, they become footnotes to positivism. They should not abandon
science either, but rather tend to it and show the way to other modes of
understanding the world. To paraphrase Georges Canguilhem, we must return
technology to life.
AD : What
about people who want to develop new technologies in order to establish a new
life in outer space? Does this also represent a cosmotechnics? For instance,
the rocket billionaires, Bezos and Musk, who dream of colonies in space and a
colonization of Mars?
YH : There
is a great passage in Nietzsche’s The Gay Science (1882), where he talks about
“the horizon of the infinite.” It describes the moderns who have abandoned land
for the pursuit of the infinite, yet, when they are in the middle of the ocean,
there is nothing more fearful than the infinite — there is no more home to
return to. The desire of the moderns, described by Nietzsche, continues to
produce an effect of disorientation, while the sentiment that there is no
longer any home to return to provides a huge market for psychotherapy and
spiritual salvation. The longing for the infinite transports us toward the
inhuman.
For
Jean-François Lyotard, there are both positive and negative infinities, which
are connected to different forms of rationality. Positive inhumanity captures
us in rigid technological systems, like we see in China with the social credit
system. The positive inhuman is one that is “more interior in myself than me” —
for example, God for St. Augustine. We humans carry something inhuman in us,
which is irreducible to the human and which maintains the highest intimacy with
us. At the outset of his book L’Inhumain (1998), Lyotard asks if the ultimate
goal for science is not that of preparing for the death of the sun, which,
granted, lies unimaginably in the future, but which also entails the
destruction of all living beings on Earth.
Rocket
billionaires, who are all transhumanists, want to overcome finitude: the
finitude of human life and of life as such. This longing for the infinite also
implies no limit to capital accumulation. Overcoming human limitations — the
search for eternal life — also implies an infinite market. In a way, the same
happens in space exploration: investors want to profit from the Earth losing
its meaning, as if leaving the planet were a matter of leaving one spaceship to
enter another. I don’t think it is wrong to explore, or to try to understand
the universe, but the conquest we see today seems to me to be merely a preparation
for tomorrow’s consumerism. Transhumanists impose on us a false choice because
they connect the question of the future of human existence with the question of
immortality and describe Earth as a mere spacecraft.
AD : In
your last book, there is a passage about the secularization of space in which
you mention that Elon Musk has launched his Tesla roadster into orbit around
the sun. You see this as the first step in the commercialization of the cosmos
and the next step as mining on other planets, effectively reducing them to mere
natural resources, raw material.
YH : As
far as I’m concerned, Elon Musk can send his car into space or even travel to
Mars, but we should not believe that these projects are the necessary next step
in a certain technological development. This doesn’t mean that I see travel in
outer space as irrelevant or dangerous in itself. Humankind has speculated for
a long time about what is out there among the twinkling stars. It is the same
curiosity that has brought forth science and technology. The progressives
choose science and the reactionaries choose tradition, but we can also choose
to follow a third path — the way of thinking.
I have
meticulously followed this third path by asking if we can begin from a
cosmological perspective and find new ways of coexisting that will allow us to
transform modern technology. My aim is not to refuse modern technology nor to
see it as a cause for uprootedness, but rather to see the irreconcilability of
technology and science with tradition as something fruitful, as a gesture I
call “tragist.” This is a main subject of my new book Art and Cosmotechnics
[published by the University of Minnesota Press in May]. The discrepancy can be
fertile soil for new thinking. In The Question Concerning Technology in China,
I try to find out how we can deploy Chinese philosophy to enable ourselves to
think differently about the contradiction between tradition and modern
technology. I hope to derive a Chinese technological thought from an
interpretation of Qi and Dao, which should not be understood as mystical
concepts but rather as frameworks for thinking about our relationship to the
nonhuman — to the 10,000 beings that Lao-Tse talks about — whereby the use of technology must follow
Dao, as a philosophy of nature and a philosophy of life.
AD : Since
the Renaissance, nature has often been reduced to something solely material and
mechanical that can be manipulated through human cunning. Is there a credible
Western alternative to such a mechanistic worldview and its associated
instrumental rationality?
YH : Romantics
and idealists in Kant’s time felt a need for something different from the
mechanistic legacy of Descartes. They found a new metaphor in the “organism.”
What we have here is an idealization of the organic, which also manifests
itself in Kant’s cosmopolitan philosophy. The idea is that if a country
misbehaves, it will be punished by losing the respect of other countries. More
concretely, it will be subjected to boycotts and embargoes. The interests of
trade make international politics into a self-regulating, organic system.
AD : In
Recursivity and Contingency, you explicitly read Kant’s organic thinking as an
early form of cybernetic theory. Heidegger famously pointed out that
cybernetics was about to take over our thinking, or at least the philosophical
form of thought that seeks to reflect upon the world and play an active role in
history. How could the idea of organic self-regulating systems look so
promising and inclusive at first, and yet end up becoming such a threat to
philosophy?
YH : Cybernetics
was promoted as an attempt to transcend the many contradictions of science.
Hans Jonas, a pupil of Heidegger, discusses this in his book The Phenomenon of
Life (1966). He said that with cybernetics we have, for the first time, a
unified theory that is not dualistic. Instead of thinking in terms of logical
contradictions, we think in terms of processes: inputs, outputs, and feedback
loops. In the 20th century, organicist thinking was further elaborated in Alfred
North Whitehead’s philosophy, but it also became a part of the practical
development of technology. Two centuries after Kant wanted to save philosophy
from the mechanical by recourse to the organic, this way of thinking has become
a part of technology. Using organic thinking, based on technology, to criticize
modern technology becomes a fallacy — a misplaced fallacy, as Whitehead would
say. When the organic already has merged with technology, cybernetic thinking
has come to an end.
AD : Do
we end up in a position where a critique of technology functions as part of the
same technological system — i.e., where criticism becomes just another piece of
input, another feedback loop programmed into the machinery? If we really think
cybernetically, when we repair or upgrade a machine, program, or mechanism, are
we not also becoming a part of the machinery, an instrument for its
improvement?
YH : Yes,
according to what we call second-order cybernetics, humans and machines are
connected in a recursive movement, which becomes an instance of what Hegel
calls a master-slave dialectic.
AD
: For Hegel, this dialectic was about
power, knowledge, and recognition. The master exploits the slave for work and
services. But who is the master and who is the slave here?
YH : Machines
are slaves but at the same time masters because human beings have to service
them and come to depend on them. Once we look at ourselves as servants of
machines, we arrive at what Hegel calls unhappy consciousness. To overcome
unhappy consciousness, we need either a Hegelian reconciliation or a
Nietzschean will to power. At the moment, however, there is difficulty in
gaining recognition from machines unless we hardcode them to unconditionally
subordinate themselves to us; this is what has been proposed in so-called
“AI-ethics.”
AD : For
us to have a real choice with respect to the growing influence of new
technologies, we also need to assume that technological evolution isn’t
determined — that is, that we could have developed radically different technologies
than those we have today. Are we really free to choose and shape tomorrow’s
technologies?
YH : History
is contingent, which means simply that it could have been otherwise. If the
Mongols had conquered the whole world, we would have a different world history,
and probably another understanding of history as such. In light of this, it’s
important to be open to different futures, to see numerous possibilities.
That the
conception we have about our technological future really matters in the present
day is something I can illustrate with a personal experience. I recently gave a
course in the philosophy of technology in Germany that had 25 students, mostly
from the humanities. I asked them: “How do you see the future given the latest
developments in artificial intelligence and genetic engineering?” Ninety
percent of them said they found our future prospects despair-inducing. The
reason is obviously that they have very determined ideas about the future — for
instance, that they will be replaced by machines. They will have to upgrade
themselves to find a place in society. Personally, I don’t think this needs to
be the answer. We shouldn’t give in to such perspectives but rather actively
resist them.
AD : Isn’t
technological determinism, so ubiquitous in Silicon Valley, just a lot of hype,
as if to say: “These disruptions are on their way, so it’s better to get ahead
of things than to bother resisting”?
YH : This
rhetoric is the reason why all these tech companies employ futurists. The worst
is Ray Kurzweil, of course, who says that that the so-called singularity is
near and by 2025 we will become immortal. I say it in all my books: we must not
give in to this kind of deterministic propaganda from Silicon Valley.
AD : What
about Elon Musk’s research program, Neuralink, which aims to connect computers
to the brain? What do you say to his argument that humans should upgrade
themselves to stay relevant when artificial intelligence starts outperforming
us?
YH : It
is very vague, if not illogical, to say that we need to be ahead of technology,
since if the “we” is humanity, then it is constituted by technology itself.
“We” will only find ourselves always being late. Human-machine interface
research has existed for a long time, and the desire to perfect the human being
(including intelligence, emotion, and lifespan) has been a major motivation for
that research, also known as transhumanism. In the past, perfecting the human
being was done through education — aesthetic training, physical discipline,
intellectual development, et cetera. In Musk’s vision, education will be
replaced by a brain-microchip apparatus. This undermines the idea of
Enlightenment humanism because microchips, instead of reason, are to mediate
between the human mind and its world.
AD : So
where do we go from here?
YH : Human
beings have created a problematic decision for themselves: “to cut” or “to
connect.” Biotechnology is introducing a new eugenics, which is at the core of
21st-century biopolitics. Enhancement of intelligence suggests better chances
for employment and success. If you remember the famous Japanese anime Ghost in
the Shell (1995), the anarchists who decided to cut were finally raided and
transformed into cyborgs.
AD : So,
what is the message here — is the general idea that we don’t have a choice to
disconnect from these biopolitical networks and impending updates to our bodies
and our lives?
YH : Precisely
because our idea of “progress” implies a historical movement toward a unified
goal, it resists all fragmentation and diversity in evolution. As a
consequence, freedom and democracy are placed under threat. On top of this, the
ideology of Silicon Valley increasingly sees freedom and democracy as
irreconcilable goals. This is the case, in particular, for the investor Peter
Thiel: for him, there is no doubt that freedom first and foremost means
economic freedom, freedom for multinational corporations. The enormous
investments in biotech are a preparation for a time when ethical limitations
will be overcome or set aside so that technologies of biological intervention
can freely circulate in the market. This is a gigantic force that everyone
feels, but nobody knows how it will manifest or how people will react. To me,
this is the point where technodiversity becomes important and decisive. If we
don’t manage to demonstrate that there are other alternatives, the
transhumanist ideology will conquer the whole world.
AD : Do
globalized and ubiquitous technologies have to become universal, in the sense
of being regarded as true, necessary, and binding?
YH : If
you read Henry Kissinger’s article “How the Enlightenment Ends,” which appeared
in a 2018 issue of The Atlantic, he discusses how the Enlightenment depended on
the new technology of the printed word to spread its philosophy. Kissinger says
that we now have technology that spreads itself, but which lacks a philosophy.
This leads to the end of the Enlightenment. There is a blind spot in this
argument, however — namely that the Enlightenment’s claim to universality
persists, even after its end, in the guise of “technology.” In that sense,
technology in itself becomes the universal. So, what we have to do is to
radicalize Kissinger’s critique by rejecting this understanding of
technological development as something given and predetermined — i.e., as
something universal.
AD : Still,
shouldn’t we be able to accommodate the best of Enlightenment humanism, which
educates us to reason and allows us to navigate between ourselves and the
world?
YH : Kissinger’s
understanding of the Enlightenment is narrowly restricted to what we call the
Age of Reason, which consisted in a fight against superstition, injustice, and
poverty. The spread of Enlightenment ideals is important to understanding
contemporary democracies. My response to Kissinger should not be understood as
a claim against the Enlightenment. The problem, rather, is that, in his
critique, he contributes to universalizing a dubious mentality. Kissinger’s
article is an invitation to conceive of a new form of politics, a new form of
technological globalization, and a new world order. Even if Kissinger’s article
strikes a critical note, it leads us into a dangerous way of thinking, into a
politics racing toward technological singularity, particularly with respect to
military technology, surveillance, and administration. In the years to come,
everything will revolve around artificial intelligence. China, Russia, and
America all strive to be the leader in this field. This development cannot
possibly be seen as a continuation of the Enlightenment. Technological
singularity is a completely apocalyptic goal.
AD : In
this respect, do globalization and the synchronization of technology represent
a world-historical level of risk? Are these factors present in the climate
crisis, given that Earth’s atmosphere absorbs the by-products of modern
technology? Can we call global warming a negative universality, as Dipesh
Chakrabarty does, defining humanity by means of a common, grand-scale
problem-complex?
YH : What
we now call the Anthropocene is a consequence of technological and industrial
expansion after World War II. The basic premise for this period of growth was
rapid industrialization. Industrialization over the last 70 years is the direct
cause of global warming and the dawning of the Anthropocene. But that doesn’t imply
that we can or should attempt to remove industry to try to solve our problems.
We have become dependent on an industrial form of life, so the only conceivable
solution is to change our industries.
As
Charles Fourier said in his time, we need to encourage a new industrial spirit.
The kind of industrialization we have today is deeply problematic because it is
so closely connected with industrial society. Constant abundance implies
constant overproduction. If we look at agriculture, this is demonstrated flagrantly
by the meat industry. Do we really need to eat this much meat? I don’t think
so. When I grew up, I had chicken only once in a while, and I didn’t complain.
We all know that the current industrial system is unsustainable.
AD : Even
those who promote organic agriculture emphasize that overproduction is harmful
due to the development of monoculture and the widespread use of chemical
fertilizers and pesticides, all of which contribute to the destruction of
biological and cultural diversity. Would you consider a variety of local
farming techniques to be an example of technodiversity?
YH : Absolutely.
If you want to avoid using pesticides, you will soon discover that there are a
number of alternative approaches, including rotations of particular
combinations of crops. There are also, for instance, specialized techniques of
breeding certain insects that will eat harmful insects. This is
technodiversity. My suggestion is that we organize a collective project to
deliberate and discuss questions concerning technodiversity and the future of
philosophy. And this is not a task for a single person — it is a task for a
whole community.
AD : Should
we conceive of this community as planetary in size? Given that the problems we
face are common to all, governance and decision-making regarding the
development of technology is part of the destiny of the Earth itself. In your
book about cybernetics, you also discuss James Lovelock and his Gaia theory.
What is the relationship between your reconsideration of modern technologies
and a planetary cybernetics?
YH : Lovelock
was a former NASA employee. He had worked at the Jet Propulsion Laboratory
doing research on the atmosphere of Mars. Comparing the lifeless desert
environment of Mars to the living Earth inspired him to develop his Gaia theory,
which says that our planet works like a cybernetic system stabilizing itself
through organic processes. He added another point: through technology we can
“wake up Gaia.” Satellites and antennas, for instance, are technical extensions
giving Gaia new senses and technological unity. We can start to understand its
workings through intelligible feedback mechanisms. The early Lovelock was a
cybernetician.
Yet even
with all of our satellites and antennae, we have yet to wake up Gaia. We have
only just begun the technification of the Earth. Since cybernetics seems to
transcend the divide between technology and nature, it is tempting to see it as
a universal solution — a new universalism. If we really were to understand the
Earth cybernetically, we would need to experiment with it, like a black box,
where we find out, through trial and error, what works and what doesn’t. But
how many times can we flirt with destroying the Earth in an effort to make that
work? If we try to use cybernetic theory to solve environmental problems, we
lose sight of the fact that our relationship to nature is integrally related to
human sensibility, for which there is little room in cybernetics. When we think
of humans and the Earth as a cybernetic system, we have already lost the world.
AD : How
so?
YH : Because
reducing the world is losing the world. This is what Heidegger calls
forgetfulness of Being. Forgetfulness is not something that happens because we
overlook Being, or because we fail to give Being a place in our understanding
of the world, but rather because we think that the whole world is transparent
and penetrable to our understanding — we think that everything can be
calculated. The first thing we need to do is to reconsider the distinction
between what is calculable and what is incalculable. Then we must learn anew
how to approach the world as the Unknown.
On
Technodiversity: A Conversation with Yuk Hui. By Anders Dunk. Los Angeles Review of Books, June 9, 2020.
No comments:
Post a Comment