In 'Intact: A Defence of the Unmodified Body' political philosopher Clare Chambers
argues that the unmodified body is a key principle of equality. While defending
our right to change our bodies, she argues that the social pressures to modify
sends a powerful message: you are not good enough. The body becomes a site of
political importance: a place where hierarchies of sex, gender, race, disability,
age and class are reinforced.
Prof
Chambers is a political philosopher specialising in feminism, contemporary
liberalism, theories of social justice, and social construction.
Within
feminism she is particularly interested in the body and beauty norms, marriage
and personal relationships, the family and the gendered division of labour, the
intersection of gender and culture, and concepts of femininity and masculinity.
Within
liberalism she is particularly interested in liberal theories of autonomy and
equality, multiculturalism and religion, the debate between political
liberalism and comprehensive liberalism, and the work of John Rawls.
Her
interests in social construction include radical theories of social
construction within feminist and post-structural thought, as well as analytical
accounts.
Professor
Clare Chambers: Freedom, Choice, and the Unmodified Body. Alpine Fellowship, September 2022.
I don’t
care that much about my appearance. I don’t waste time chasing after arbitrary
beauty standards. I get my hair done, though, and I’ve started to have it
coloured since I turned 40, but that’s very low maintenance: four times a year,
£150 a time. And it only needs to be washed and blow-dried two or three times a
week.
I have a
skincare regime, because who doesn’t? Very simple: just wash, serum, sunscreen
in the morning; cream cleanser, gel cleanser, retinol treatment and face oil at
night. But I don’t wear makeup every day: just a light layer, three or four
times a week, which takes about five minutes. (A full face takes 20 minutes,
but I’ll only bother with that once a week.)
Leg and
underarm shaving is optional — hey, I’m a feminist! Once or twice a week. It’s
just nice not to be hairy if I’m going to the gym, which I do three times a
week for about an hour a time, but that’s about fitness as much as appearance.
It’s not like I’m having fillers or Botox or plastic surgery. I love myself the
way I am. I just spend hundreds of hours and thousands of pounds every year to
achieve it.
Listing
everything I do for beauty makes me sound, I know, unserious. If you’re a man,
you may feel incredulous at this litany of vanity. Possibly you’re wondering
how I have the time or the money for these commitments. If you’re a woman,
though — even if you’re a woman who has opted out of all this stuff — then you
will recognise the pressure to go along with it.
Nora
Ephron called it “maintenance”, in a 2005 essay: “Maintenance is what you have
to do just so you can walk out the door.” More recently, the philosopher Clare
Chambers has coined a new word for the daily effort we expend on our bodies. In
her new book Intact: A Defence of the Unmodified Body, she calls it
“shametenance”.
But
what’s so shameful about the unmaintained face? Many men insist that they
prefer the “natural look” in women; then again, far fewer men demonstrate a
preference for women with grey hair, wrinkles and hairy armpits. When a female
celebrity gets papped without makeup, it’s a conspicuous enough event to make
the Mail’s sidebar of shame. A bare female face is an invitation to ask: can
she get away with it?
This,
though, is a time of exceptional frankness about the work of femininity.
Maintenance is no longer cloistered in dressing rooms, but out there in
Instagram stories and TikTok tutorials. Actresses no longer pretend their
extended youthfulness comes only from nothing but sleep and hydration; instead,
they try to sell us things.
Being
obviously beautiful can now be a full-time job. Very few influencers bother
with the tedious fiction that their desirable “skinny-thicc” figures (narrow
waist, full hips, big tits and behind) are the lucky outcome of good genes and
exercise. Instead, they put up sponsored posts about the surgeon who did their
Brazilian butt lift (BBL).
And so,
if honesty about beauty can eliminate some feelings of inadequacy, it only
replaces them with a shopping list for becoming adequate. If the idea of the
“natural look” has been debunked, it’s only allowed the most extreme and
graphic plastic surgery to be normalised. Meanwhile, the “shametenance” list
grows ever longer. These days you can get fillers at your family dentist.
And the
more routine these interventions seem, the more people want them, even at
considerable risk. If you can’t afford Botox from a medical professional in a
clinic, an unqualified practitioner working in their living room can inject an
unlicensed alternative into you instead. Victims of this black market suffer
infections, sores and permanent scarring. For every 6,000 women who have a BBL,
one or two will die as a result. It’s still the fastest-growing cosmetic
surgery in the world.
Maybe
there’s an argument that the BBL is at least a rejection of the “waif” beauty
standard formed in the Nineties and Noughties. In Sexual Revolution, Laurie
Penny writes: “Today, the ideal woman takes up as little space as possible. She
is fragile, breakable, thin and hungry-looking.” But that is not what the
“ideal woman” looks like in 2022. If it were, women would not be spending
thousands of pounds for a big bum and a non-zero chance of an embolism.
If the
thinness of the waif was the point, then the skinny-thicc look ought to be
liberatory: it’s all about having an ass that takes up as much space as
possible. But the difference in the ultimate appearance of these ideals is
irrelevant. What matters is that both advertise, through their exaggerated
aesthetic, the effort that went into them: a waif is waifish because she
scrupulously manages her food intake, a skinny-thicc is skinny-thicc because
she’s put in the hours on the operating table.
In 2004,
the sex advice columnist Dan Savage was asked about another fashion in female
body shape: why weren’t women in porn getting enormous, “bigger-than-your-head”
breast implants anymore? And this is what he replied:
“The sudden appearance of women with
ridiculously huge boob implants was arousing in part because of its shock
value. There was the shock of women with such exaggerated racks, of course, but
there was also the more important and, sadly, the infinitely more arousing
shock of women finding a novel new way to imperil their health in order to
attract the attention of men.”
The
point of all these extremes is their demonstration of commitment to being
beautiful — to fulfilling the assumption, as Chambers describes it, that “to be
a woman is to be sexually attractive, or at least to be sexually available, or
at least open to judgement for being or not being sexually attractive and
available”. It’s not that these physiques are universally desired by men at the
times they become popular. It’s that they become the accepted symbol of a
woman’s willingness to reshape her body in order to be pleasing.
Trends
are cyclical: an aesthetic gains ascendency, spreads to ubiquity, is pushed to
absurdity in the competition for attention, and then collapses under the
physical limitations of the body to be replaced by the next standard. When the
thing after skinny-thicc begins to emerge, it might feel like an escape, but it
won’t be. It will go through the same process, have the same distribution of
winners and losers, exhaust itself the same way.
Women’s
bodies, in other words, will always be a problem to solve. They will never be
acceptable. That’s what makes Chambers’s position in Intact so appealingly
radical: she argues that bodies do not need to be modified. Your body is
valuable just as it is, because it is you. And I agree — while being enormously
grateful that Chambers leaves enough flexibility in her thesis for me to agree
without having to change any of the habits I’m attached to.
Intact
is not absolutist. Sometimes, writes Chambers, modification is justified — for
reasons of health or happiness. So it’s okay to spend £150 getting my hair
done, because it’s a pleasure. (I’m a primate: it’s nice to be groomed. The
sociological term for this is “the beauty touch”, says Chambers.) It’s okay for
me to lift weights in the gym; so long as steroids aren’t involved:
“bodybuilding can be good for both body and soul.” My tattoos are perhaps a
more challenging case, but they too are defensible for Chambers as acts of
“self-expression”.
In fact,
any kind of body modification turns out to be acceptable in the end, because
“the principle of the unmodified body asserts a premise, not a goal”. This
saves her from doing anything as gauche as telling other people what to do with
their bodies, but it does set her argument a little adrift: her book is part
passionate defence of physical integrity, part “you do you” shrug.
Chambers
is also careful to make a fine distinction between “unmodified” and “natural”,
pointing out that the latter is an unhelpful concept because “if being natural
means being without human interference, then no human and no body can ever be
natural”. Everything you consume, every movement you make, can alter the
appearance of your body. How can a woman decide what to do with her body when
every possible choice is loaded with value?
I’m not
as scared of being censorious as Chambers is. As far as I’m concerned, wanting
to change your appearance is part of being human, and one of the ways we signal
status and group loyalty. But not all modifications are equal, and the ones we
should be wary of are, first, the ones that infringe on the body’s ability to
be a body: that destroy its capacity for function or pleasure (labiaplasty),
that attack its self-reliance by turning it into a permanent patient (fillers
that must be endlessly refilled so the stretched-out cavity won’t sag).
We
should also be suspicious of modifications that distort our idea of the
average. If you want Botox and can afford the good stuff, I do chafe at the
idea of banning it. However, and as Chambers argues, we should not pretend the
ethics here end with individual choice: if you eliminate your fine lines, you
will change how others feel about theirs. When you’ve seen enough strangely
ageless faces, your own normal creases begin to feel like deformities.
And
finally, we should query modifications that are displays of pure female
submission — by which I mean the extreme and dangerous forms of plastic
surgery, but which arguably includes a great many of the less intrusive things
I do. Chambers describes makeup as the ultimate in self-objectification,
because when we wear it, “we see ourselves as others see us, and treat their
perspective as the one that counts”.
I baulk
at this — my face is a means of communication, and makeup is a fun way to play
with the vocabulary of expression — but I should, at least, accept the
possibility that I might be wrong. Beauty may be laborious. But declining to do
beauty is its own kind of hard. In a society that judges women in particular so
harshly on the way they look, it’s an announcement of non-compliance, and it’s
often met with hostility.
The
point is, even when a woman decides she will not make a statement with her
body, she is making a statement. The point is, this is exhausting. The point
is, it’s supposed to be: even on the days I’m not spending hours in a salon or
carefully painting wings along my lash line, I’m still distractedly thinking
about how I look at least some of the time. And if I stopped thinking about it?
Someone else would still be thinking about it for me, judging me. The point is,
there is no way out. We’re damned if we care, and damned if we don’t.
Women
can’t be beautiful : Whatever we do to our bodies, it's wrong. By Sarah Ditum.
Unherd, February 28, 2022.
Oppressors,
as a rule, deny oppressed people their own ‘native’ standards of beauty,” Susan
Sontag once wrote. Intact: A Defence of the Unmodified Body is the Cambridge
philosopher Clare Chambers’s attempt to take aim at the ideal the oppressors have
cooked up for women. In place of the usual thin, buxom blonde, she presents an
alternative idol—“the unmodified body,” a physique that has not been winnowed
by diets, enhanced by plastic surgeries, or chiseled by grueling exercise
regimens. The unmodified body may not be especially thin; it may eschew makeup
and feminine clothing; it may even openly menstruate. The unmodified body takes
as many forms as there are people, but each iteration is distinguished by being
“good enough just as it is”—the moral leitmotif that echoes throughout Intact.
Chambers
is well aware that body modification is by no means forced upon us: in her
first book, Sex, Culture, and Justice (2008), she emphasizes that “women comply
with appearance norms to an extent because doing so is, in myth and reality,
pleasurable.” Here, as elsewhere, she is less concerned with overt coercion,
which is easy enough to identify and condemn, and more distressed by the subtle
pressures that skulk in the vicinity of our ostensible choices like predators
waiting to pounce. Women appear to choose diets and uncomfortable shoes, but do
they really? And must we respect a choice that is sufficiently degrading? The
antagonist of Sex, Culture, and Justice is traditional liberalism, which the
book caricatures rather uncharitably as worshipful of any state of affairs that
comes about by choice. Yet, Chambers counters, we have only to think of women
with eating disorders to see that some freely undertaken modifications are
still ethically suspect. Hence the need for a feminist renovation of the
liberal shibboleths: we should not honor choices fomented under patriarchal
conditions or choices incompatible with human dignity, even if no one is
holding a gun to anyone else’s head.
In
Intact, the enemy is no longer traditional liberalism and its defenders but
demeaning choices themselves—that is, choices made with an eye to improvement
or beautification. Chambers defends her rubric in three lengthy sections:
“Natural,” “Normal,” and “Whole.” While naturalness and normalcy do not
perfectly overlap with the unmodified body, they are not unrelated. Chambers
calls both concepts “frenemies,” insofar as they are sometimes politically
profitable and sometimes apt for abuse. (We might ask, what concept isn’t?) The
natural hair movement, which encourages Black women to celebrate their
distinctively textured hair, is a friend, but the natural makeup movement, a
trend encouraging women to apply inconspicuous cosmetics, is an enemy; removing
the stigma of menstruation by deeming the phenomenon “normal” is a friend,
while efforts to denigrate disabilities as “abnormal” are enemies. Matters come
to a head in the “Whole” section, which tackles the question of how we should
approach the decision to modify both our bodies and those of our dependents.
The
writing along the way can be animated—unlike most philosophers, Chambers
ventures out of the arm chair and into the fray, interviewing plastic surgeons,
attending bodybuilding competitions, and speaking to women who have had
mastectomies—but it can also be needlessly scholastic, laden with gratuitous
distinctions and embarrassing coinages like “shametenance,” a portmanteau of
“shame” and “maintenance.” Readers may lose track of the plot as they are
dragged off on long digressions that that never make their way back to the
book’s central thesis.
Even
without the excurses on feminist critiques of the natural, however, the book’s
central thesis would be maddeningly difficult to locate. Is the unmodified body
a standard-bearer for real bodies, a regulative ideal that actual anatomy can
at best approximate, or something else altogether? And whether it is ethereal
or effluvial, is it interesting or useful?
Chambers
cannot quite decide what the unmodified body amounts to: it is “not only
something that exists in the world as a real, material object,” she writes in
Intact’s introduction; “it is also an idea that is constructed by political
processes.”
But what
“real, material object” is ever “unmodified”? Time alone is sufficient to sag
the skin, and even bare maintenance requires alteration. “Everything we do, or
don’t do, has an effect,” as Chambers acknowledges. Whether we eat or don’t
eat, tan or don’t tan, shower or don’t shower, cut our hair or let it grow, the
flesh bears testament. How, then, can the proprietor of an “unmodified” body
afford to eat, age, or exercise? And what about medical treatments? For
Chambers, only some modifications end up counting as such, and medical
interventions are generally exempt from opprobrium: she concedes that “heart
attacks, cancer and infectious diseases are matters of health” in want of
treatment, yet she neglects to explain why these afflictions merit modification
when others do not, or whether there is any general metric for distinguishing
acceptable interventions from illicit ones.
Intact
is rife with richly sketched and entertaining examples, but they are never
sorted according to precise principles. Chambers vehemently disapproves of
breast enlargement, but she ambivalently supports the small but growing number
of women who choose to tattoo their bare chests in the wake of mastectomies,
though both procedures are not medical but aesthetic. Despite her enthusiasm
for the natural hair movement, Chambers concedes that “natural” coiffure is in
fact no more “natural” than subtle eye shadow styles, given that both are
require effort and artistry. Sometimes, Chambers claims that we must intervene
to restore the body to its unmodified state; for this reason, she is in favor
of reconstructive surgery for patients who are suddenly disfigured. Yet she
never tells us why the body that exists prior to an accident should qualify as
any more “unmodified” than the same body in its aftermath. If our physiques are
in constant flux, why should a person’s condition immediately before an injury
count as her baseline? Why isn’t the default her body after her mishap, or her
body when she was sixteen? Instead of venturing any answers, Intact makes a
virtue of its refusal to take a stance. From the knotty case of cochlear implants,
which endow deaf children with a sense that approximates hearing at the cost of
isolating them from the Deaf community, Chambers infers “there is no simple
answer to the question of whether a modification is valuable.” She is right, of
course, but we turn to philosophy not for pat reminders of complexity but for
some measure of clarification.
Often,
when Chambers is pressed to issue a verdict about a particular procedure, she
beats a hasty retreat to abstraction, claiming that the unmodified body is “a
complex political concept, not a simple material thing.” She goes so far as to
deem it a “principle,” though she offers no straightforward statement of the
principle it is. (There is also no explanation of how something as ethereal as
a principle can be transubstantiated into a “real, material object.”) Chambers
is perhaps at her most perspicuous when she writes, “my argument is not that
modification is always wrong, or even that it is presumptively suspect.”
Rather, her argument is that “we must take collective action against the
pressures to modify.” We might extrapolate that the principle of the unmodified
body permits only freely chosen interventions, but Chambers directly
contradicts this interpretation elsewhere, insisting in the introduction that “the
unmodified body should be defended as a default” and, later, that “the whole
body should be treated as the default that it is.” So is modification
presumptively suspect, or isn’t it? Is the “intact” body an idea or a sack of
blood and bones?
Whether
this mysterious construct turns out to be an incorporeal concept or a tangible
tangle of ligaments, the core imperative of Intact is that we must regard it as
good enough, however difficult it may be to inhabit. Chambers provides several
rationales for this injunction. The first is that there is a necessary
connection between valuing a person’s physique and valuing a person: because
“the body is us,” “treating people equally means asserting the political
principle of the value of the unmodified body.” The second is that “rejecting
the concept of nature and the realities of bodies makes us unable to theorize
the way that those bodies operate in the world.” Although the natural body is
not quite the same as the unmodified body, the two notions are neighboring—and,
according to Chambers, only by embracing some hybrid can we confront our
materiality.
How,
then, are we to honor the body as “good enough as it is”? If we are not
required to reject modifications out of hand, what are we required to do?
Chambers emphasizes that individual actions are not enough to reform a culture
that is collectively constructed and sustained, but she does not really reckon
with the aesthetic hold that others retain over us, and she provides little
guidance as to how broader reforms—especially of “the political and economic
structures that set us up to feel bad”—might come about. Instead, she urges us
to express respect for our trappings (and thereby ourselves) by scrutinizing
our reasons for craving modification; should we discover that we are acting in
deference to undue social pressure, we should suffer to remain as we are.
About
others’ bodies, we are called upon to exercise even more caution: if we find
ourselves in a position to make decisions for those who cannot consent to
medical care, such as children, we can opt for modification only if “1), the
evidence that the intervention is in [the patient’s] best interests is beyond
reasonable doubt, or 2), there is clear and convincing evidence that the
intervention best secures that person’s right to an open future.” As Chambers
sees it, that means we are obligated to keep a child alive, but we are not
permitted to give trans children hormone-blockers, to circumcise Jewish and
Muslim babies, or to pierce a pre-verbal infant’s ears. In the last section of
the book, which is dedicated to practical prescriptions, we appear to have
exited the domain of principle and returned once again to the concrete question
of when to consign someone to a flesh-and-blood body that she finds unbearable.
By the
end of Intact, it is hard to escape the conclusion that Chambers has
gerrymandered the conceptual terrain so as to exclude modifications that peeve
her and permit modifications that please her. Why should hormone therapy—a
course of treatment that strikes many physicians (not to mention parents) as
quite resoundingly in the “best interests” of trans children, indeed as
necessary to ensure them an “open future”—come in for special censure, when
plenty of comparable procedures are not even mentioned? There is no obvious
reason to regard the body of an infant wearing an unwieldly brace to correct
scoliosis as any more “intact” than that of a child on hormone blockers—or, for
that matter, a child on supplements, a child using skin creams to combat
eczema, and so on and on.
Indeed,
I am skeptical that there is such a thing as an “intact” body, even in
principle. It is hard to imagine a way of shaping our offspring’s
lives—enrolling them in dance classes or sports, feeding them more or less
nutritious diets, slathering them with sunscreen at the beach, offering them
vegetarian fare instead of meat or meat instead of vegetables, paving their
mouths with orthodontic correctives, rewhirling the whorls of their brains by
making them fiddle with Rubik’s Cubes—that does not also shape their bodies.
But if the unmodified body is a patent impossibility, why should we waste time
aspiring to realize it?
Chambers
might respond by reminding us that the unmodified body is an idea without
viscera. But she is the one who infers from the principle—together with her own
interpretation of the available evidence—that we should not provide real
children, who are not unfeeling principles but embodied persons, with
gender-affirming care. And while there is surely such a thing as a fruitful
fiction, for instance a predictively effective model in science, the unmodified
body remains wrongheaded even when it has been demoted from material to myth.
All of the nominal benefits of Chambers’s view can be captured without appeal
to an entity so dubious. If the problem is not modification itself but undue
pressures to modify, then we would do better to articulate an alternative
principle—the principle of the freely modified body, for instance, or perhaps
the principle of unpressured modification. Nor do we need to accept a person’s
body in its current form in order to regard her as a political equal, any more
than we need to embrace everything about someone’s personality in order to hold
her in high regard. To suggest that a friend should be more considerate toward
her partner or more diligent in her studies is not to suggest that she is
worthless or without moral dignity. Even if “the body is us” (the avid
italicization is Chambers’s), the notion that we ought to change some things
about ourselves is perfectly compatible with the notion that we are deserving
of fundamental respect.
Chambers
frets that “rejecting the concept of nature and the realities of bodies makes
us unable to theorize the way that those bodies operate in the world”—but declining
to make a fetish of the “natural” (or the unmodified) is not equivalent to
rejecting “the realities of bodies.” A modified body is still a body, still a
locus of sensual attention. I would go so far as to suggest that many
modification practices are part and parcel of giving physicality its due. The
bodybuilders to whom Chambers devotes a chapter spend hours each day enhancing
their physiques, and they are more achingly aware of their musculature as a
result. Many of my favorite drag queens apply ornate makeup and thereby come to
stand in a painterly relation to their faces, yet it never occurs to Chambers
that successful self-stylization is sometimes an aesthetic achievement, a way
of elevating raw anatomy to art.
Occasionally,
Intact is not just theoretically inert and artistically bankrupt but outright
regressive. Chambers sounds like the worst sort of conservative paranoiac when
she concludes,
“”if the
morally privileged baseline were the modified body as opposed to the unmodified
one we would be locked into a duty to seek constant modification, constant
enhancement, unending surgery or self-improvement or technological advance.
There would be no principled end.””
But
slopes are not always slippery: this inference is simply specious. To conclude
that some scintilla of body modification is inevitable, and that freely
endorsed modifications can be positive, is certainly not to impose a duty for
unending modification on anyone. Worse still, such conspiratorial
fear-mongering often forms the basis of maudlin and all-too-familiar elegies to
finitude that have frequently shaded into screeds against reproductive autonomy
(contraception is evil), gay sex (what’s next, bestiality?), and, especially
today, gender-affirming surgery (which is the first step, we are told, on the
road to transhumanism). Chambers is apparently unbothered by her argument’s
resemblance to these insidious insinuations, yet they are of a piece. Few
conservatives insist that we must decline cancer treatment in order to embrace
our vulnerability, but plenty argue that women who use contraception are
asserting technocratic dominance over the natural order of things rather than
heroically confronting the fact of human limitation. Chambers makes similarly
invidious arguments, condoning cancer treatment but condemning treatments for
gender dysphoria, without justification. She might as well follow
feminist-turned-reactionary Louise Perry, who laments, in a recent polemic
about the ills of the sexual revolution, that liberalism “seeks to free individuals
from the external constraints placed on us by location, family, religion,
tradition, and even (and most relevant to feminists) the human body.”
But just
as it is false that liberals who hope to protect some kernel of autonomy aspire
to exert total sovereignty over the world, and just as it is false that
providing trans people with gender-affirming care will usher in an era of
cyborgs, it is false that rejecting the standard set by Intact is to succumb to
rampant, ceaseless modification. When it comes to assessing a bodily
intervention, the degree to which the body will be modified is not the right
metric—which is not necessarily to say that there is no metric or that anything
goes.
The
right standard is not that of bodily purity but that of aesthetic agency.
Sontag identified the crux of the matter when she observed that oppressors
impose beauty standards on the populations they colonize. The problem is not
that we modify our bodies at all, a tic we could scarcely excise so long as we
go on exercising and excreting, but that most people have little power over the
standards by which their modified bodies are to be assessed. As Wordsworth
writes in a supplement to the “Preface to Lyrical Ballads,” “every author, as
far as he is great and at the same time original, has had the task of creating
the taste by which he is to be enjoyed.” The true injustice of the present
norms is that women and people of color are enmeshed in a net of their
oppressors’ poor taste.
Of
course, it is no trifling matter to determine which of our aesthetic
propensities are really our own (or at least, enough our own), nor is it easy
to relinquish the standards of our milieu, even on the rare occasions when we
have succeeded in disentangling them from the snarled skein of desire. Chambers
is right to worry that women in particular face obstacles to the cultivation of
aesthetic agency, as well as plenty of material incentives to accept
patriarchal blueprints demanding they shrink their waists and inflate their
busts.
But if
women are tyrannized by dint of having no hand in crafting the criteria by
which they are judged, then even well-meaning paternalism is not a solution.
The content of Chambers’s proposal may be less punishing than that of the
patriarchal project (at least for some), but she is merely substituting a more
benign dictatorship for a more barbarous one. Instead of embracing a
presumption against modification, we should embrace a commitment to realizing
aesthetic autonomy and enabling artistic imagination for all.
Because,
if there were such a thing as an unmodified body, who would want one? It would
be inert, untouched by the ordeal of living, almost inanimate. Worse, it would
be artless, one more refusal to sanctify the world by beautifying it. The drag
queens whose cosmetic skills I find so impressive present a better model. They
have every motive to become drab or, worse, vulgarly virile, but instead they
muster the courage and imagination to render themselves dazzling—an aesthetic
merit that smacks of moral courage at a time when neo-fascists prowl in wait
outside drag queen story hours. Like all the best artworks, they invent not
only themselves but new sensibilities for themselves. Reactionaries are right,
in a way, to fear them. They leave no one who sees them intact.
A Body
of One’s Own : Feminist arguments against body modification are a dead end. By
Becca
Rothfeld. Boston Review, March 1, 2023.