In the
17th and 18th centuries, a group of Western philosophers came to clashes, on
the page at least, over the age-old problem of evil: the question of how a good
God could allow the existence of evil and suffering in the world. Philosophers
such as Pierre Bayle, Nicolas Malebranche and G W Leibniz, later followed by
such pillars of the canon as Voltaire, David Hume and Immanuel Kant, vehemently
disagreed not only on how the problem could be solved – if it could be solved
at all – but also on how to speak of such dark matters.
Some of
these arguments of ‘theodicy’ (the attempt to justify creation) may seem
antiquarian to modern eyes – but in an age where young people question the
morality of bringing new children into the world, they are surprisingly relevant.
After all, the issue is not just about God: it is about creation and, more
specifically, the extent to which creation can be justified, given the ills or
‘evils’ that are in the world.
The
question of creation is urgent for us today. Considering the great
uncertainties of the climate crisis, is it justified to create new people, not
knowing what kind of future lies ahead of them? And if it is justified, is
there any point at which it ceases to be? Most people would probably agree that
some worlds are imaginable in which creation would be immoral. At what precise
point is life too bad, or too uncertain, to pass on?
In the
early Enlightenment, of course, there were no such concerns for the future of
the planet. But there were evils in existence – plenty of them. Crimes,
misfortunes, death, disease, earthquakes and the sheer vicissitudes of life.
Considering such evils, these philosophers asked, can existence still be
justified?
This
longstanding philosophical debate is where we get the terms ‘optimism’ and
‘pessimism’, which are so much used, and perhaps overused, in our modern
culture. ‘Optimism’ was the phrase coined by the Jesuits for philosophers such
as Leibniz, with his notion that we live in ‘the best of all possible worlds’
(for surely, if God could have created a better one, he would have done so).
‘Pessimism’ followed not long afterwards to denote philosophers such as
Voltaire, whose novel Candide (1759) ridiculed Leibnizian optimism by
contrasting it with the many evils in the world. ‘If this is the best of all
possible worlds,’ Voltaire’s hero asks, ‘what on earth are the others like?’
But
really, Voltaire wasn’t much of a pessimist: other philosophers such as Bayle
and Hume went much further in their demonstrations of the badness of existence.
For Bayle, and for Hume after him, the point is not just that the evils of life
outnumber the goods (though they believe this is also the case), but that they
outweigh them. A life might consist of an equal number of good moments and bad
moments: the problem is that the bad moments tend to have an intensity that
upsets the scales. A small period of badness, says Bayle, has the power to ruin
a large amount of good, just like a small portion of seawater can salt a barrel
of fresh water. Similarly, one hour of deep sorrow contains more evil than
there is good in six or seven pleasant days.
Against
that bleak vision, thinkers such as Leibniz and Jean-Jacques Rousseau
emphasised the goods of life, and the power we have to seek out the good in all
things, for if we learned to adjust our vision we would see that life is in
fact very good: that ‘there is incomparably more good than evil in the life of
men, as there are incomparably more houses than prisons,’ Leibniz writes, and
that the world ‘will serve us if we use it for our service; we shall be happy
in it if we wish to be.’ Just as the pessimists believed the optimists were
deceived in their insistence on the goods of life, so too the optimists thought
the pessimists’ eyes were skewed towards the bad: each side accused the other
of not having the right vision.
A large
part of the question thus became: what is the right vision?
One
thing that struck me as I dug deeper into these questions was how concerned
both the optimists and the pessimists were with the ethical assumptions
underlying the theoretical arguments. On the surface, the question was: can
creation be justified? But beneath it, never far removed, lay a deeper
question, a question just as ethically and emotionally imbued: how to speak of
suffering in a way that offers hope and consolation?
There is
not just a theoretical, but also a moral objection that each side makes against
the other. The great objection that the pessimists lay at the feet of the
optimists is that to insist that life is good even in the face of hard,
unyielding suffering, or to stipulate that we are in control of our happiness,
that we shall be happy ‘if we wish to be’ – that this is to make our suffering
worse. It is to add to suffering the responsibility for that suffering; it is
to burden the sufferer with a sense of their inadequacy. If life is so good,
then the sufferer’s trials must be a case of wrong vision – and indeed the
optimists tend to say things just like that. This is why optimism, so say the
pessimists, is a cruel philosophy. If it gains us some hope, it fails in
consolation.
But on
their side, the optimists prove to be similarly concerned. Their objection to
the pessimists is that, if we insist on the intensity and ubiquity and
inescapability of suffering, if we describe it in all its depths and bleakness
(as the pessimists indeed are wont to do), this heaps suffering on suffering –
and it is this that makes suffering worse, as ‘evils are doubled by being given
an attention that ought to be averted from them,’ as Leibniz says.
Pessimism,
so say the optimists, is itself unconsoling – but more than that, it is
unhopeful.
The
question concerning these philosophers, then, is not just the theoretical one
about whether life in general is good or bad, but also a more concrete one:
face to face with one who suffers, what can philosophy bring to the table? What
can philosophy offer in the way of hope and consolation?
Both
strands of thought have the same aim, but they plot different routes to get
there: the pessimists offer consolation by emphasising our fragility, by
recognising that no matter how hard we try, we may fail to achieve happiness,
for no fault of our own. Meanwhile, the optimists seek to unfold hope by
emphasising our capacity, by insisting that no matter how dark, how bleak our
circumstances, we can always change our vision and direction, we can always aim
for better.
Of
course, there is no reason in principle why both roads could not be combined,
each to serve as the necessary counterpart for the other, an antidote for the
poison each draught may become when served up undiluted. But the fact remains
that these earliest optimists and pessimists saw them as opposed – and in fact
we do too: we still have the tendency to think in binary terms, as if there is
in life a stark choice to be made between optimism and pessimism, or, in Noam
Chomsky’s words, for optimism or despair:
“We have
two choices. We can be pessimistic, give up, and help ensure that the worst
will happen. Or we can be optimistic, grasp the opportunities that surely
exist, and maybe help make the world a better place. Not much of a choice.”
That
last example itself makes manifest the coarseness and onesidedness of our use
of these terms. Optimism tends to be positively charged, pessimism negatively charged.
When we call someone an optimist, it’s usually praise. This is why politicians
are particularly keen to insist that they are optimists, or even to speak of a
‘duty of optimism’. Conversely, to call someone a pessimist is usually to
deride, denounce, deflate them. ‘Pessimism is for losers,’ as one recent book
title has it.
But are
our choices so dichotomous? If there are shadows on the road of pessimism,
there are dangers on the opposite road also. And these are the very dangers
that those older pessimists kept warning us against: that if we overemphasise
the power we have over our minds, our lives, our destinies, it is all too easy
to stumble into cruelty.
We need
not look very far to see examples of what optimism, in its darkest forms, can
become. When a 2008 London tower block named Heygate Estate was sold off to
foreign investors, its inhabitants were first evicted then offered mindfulness
courses by the local council to deal with their anxiety, so that they were
themselves made responsible for their misfortunes. If we are each radically in
control of our mental states, what reason is there to ask for social justice?
This is the shadow-side that cleaves to the popular narrative that ‘you are
responsible for your own happiness’, and is bolstered by the subtle terror of a
social media regime that pushes us to broadcast our success and happiness to
the world.
It is in
such cases that the consoling force of pessimism reveals itself: it’s OK to not
be OK. Sometimes we fail, sometimes we run up against the hard walls of our own
capacities or the world’s boundaries – and it can be consoling to be reminded
that our suffering, our fragility, is not our fault. That we suffer despite
ourselves. That it can be right to grieve for what we are losing, or are yet to
lose, or have already lost.
We are
so quick to equate pessimism with passivity or fatalism or despair, and to
reject it on that basis – for, of course, we do not want a philosophy that
tells us to give up. But is that really what pessimism means? As Joshua Foa
Dienstag argued in his book Pessimism: Philosophy, Ethic, Spirit (2006), far
from leading to passivity, pessimism can be closely linked to a tradition of
moral and political activism, as in the case of Albert Camus, whose courage and
activism in the Second World War were infused by his pessimistic views.
Even the
darkest pessimists never said that life would only get worse or can never be
better: this is a caricature of pessimism, sketched quickly to dismiss it.
Arthur Schopenhauer, the bleakest of them all, did not subscribe to it. On the
contrary, he suggested that it is precisely because we cannot control the
course of things that we can never know what the future holds: life may become
worse or better. ‘The pessimist,’ in Dienstag’s words, ‘expects nothing.’ There
is not much hope in this, perhaps, but it is a kind of hope nevertheless. And
so too is the faint glimmering that can be found amid the darkest pages of
these writers: the quick unquiet intuition that something can be gathered in the
black vision; that our eyes may be opened in ways they were not before; that we
may see in the darkness.
It is
why hopeful pessimism may not be a contradiction, but a manifestation of the
wild power that is harnessed only when life’s darkest forces are gathered into
the strange alchemy of hope.
I think
about these things in this age marked by ecological depletion and devastation,
by floods and fires and heat ceilings that no one had thought possible, by the
spectre of the climate crisis that takes shape all around us. This age is
marked also by the quiet, or not so quiet, desperation of the young. The same
criticisms once waged against the pessimists of yore are now laid at the feet
of the despairing young by those techno-optimists and advocates of progress for
whom any consideration of the mere possibility of decline is itself a sign of
weakness, a lack of imagination, a moral flaw – a failure of vision, most of
all. And so they denounce young people’s outcry as pessimism, as fatalism, as
‘mere’ despair. They criticise them for the bleakness of their vision, call
their statements exaggerated and the speakers spoiled.
It is
all too easy to miss the fact that this generation – the first to grow up in a
world where a climate emergency is not just on the horizon, but a stark reality
– is haunted by a real sense of losing the future, as all the things they have
been told give life meaning are rendered either pointless or problematic.
Things like: study, get a good job, settle down – but what jobs are still certain?
Where will it be safe to settle down? As Greta Thunberg said in Parliament
Square in London in 2018: ‘And why should I be studying for a future that soon
will be no more, when no one is doing anything whatsoever to save that future?’
Things like: start a family – but if there is no future for one’s children, is
it still OK to procreate? Even more trivial things, like developing oneself by
travelling, are no longer straightforward: for how important is
self-development when weighed against the carbon cost of modern travel?
This is
a wholesale collapse of meaning that is only now becoming clear to us. There is
a very real sense in which young people are experiencing not only the loss of
concepts, but the loss of the future itself, as all the usual answers to the
question of what makes life worthwhile become increasingly uncertain. They are
in that darkness, searching for some kind of hope, some kind of consolation –
and what can we offer them? Surely we can do better than give the manifestly
inadequate answer (which may also be an outright lie) to assure them that all
will be well – since we know there is every chance it won’t be.
Any
crude statements of optimism would be more than misplaced: it would be the kind
of lie that deceives no one, least of all the sharpened moral senses of the
young, who see through the empty promises and reassurances of politicians with
an anger we know is justified. If we told them that everything will be OK,
these are less than empty words: they are a failure to take their experience
seriously, and that, as the pessimists would tell us, is the one thing
guaranteed to make their suffering worse.
But if
brute optimism fails – could pessimism do better? I have suggested that
pessimism can have value – but could we go further? Could it be, in fact, a
virtue?
To some,
the very notion of a virtue of pessimism may seem absurd. For instance, we may
subscribe to Hume’s notion that the mark of any virtue is that it is useful and
agreeable, either to the person who possesses it or to others. But surely
pessimism is neither useful nor agreeable. It is not useful, the argument goes,
because it renders us passive, depresses not only ourselves but ‘our sense of
the possible’, as Marilynne Robinson has said of cultural pessimism in particular.
And it is not agreeable, since it intensifies our suffering, making us focus on
the bad side of life rather than the good (or so arch-optimists such as Leibniz
and Rousseau would have it). It is not surprising, then, that certain studies
of supposed ‘moral exemplars’ identified positivity, hopefulness and optimism
among the characteristics that such exemplars had in common.
But
then, think of Greta Thunberg. If there is such a thing as a ‘climate virtue’,
she would seem to exemplify it – considering the hard personal choices that she
has made, the steadfastness of her vision, and the courage with which she holds
world leaders to account and takes them to task for their half-heartedness,
their unwillingness to commit fully to the cause. If this is not an exercise of
virtues, then I don’t know what is – and yet there is nothing positive or
optimistic about Thunberg. If there is hope, it’s a dark, bleak hope, full of
rage and grief and pain for what is being lost – but infused also with
insistence, perdurance, determination. It is clear that this activist, at
least, will continue to strive even if her efforts are doomed to fail. This is
not optimism: if anything, it is a hopeful pessimism, and I believe it has
every right to be called a virtue in our age.
Hopeful
pessimism breaks through the rusted dichotomy of optimism vs pessimism. It is
this attitude, this perspective that is exemplified in Thunberg and other
figures who by their example give an affirmative answer to the question posed
by Paul Kingsnorth: ‘Is it possible to see the future as dark and darkening
further; to reject false hope and desperate pseudo-optimism without collapsing
into despair?’
The
thing to avoid is not so much pessimism, but hopelessness or fatalism or giving
up. Even despair need not be completely avoided, since it too can energise and
encourage us to strive for change, but we should avoid the kind of despair that
causes us to collapse. These things are not the same as pessimism, which is
simply the assumption of a dark view of the present as well as the future and
does not imply the loss of courage or insistence to strive for better: on the
contrary, often these are the very gifts that pessimism can bestow.
One can
be deeply, darkly pessimistic, one can find oneself in the cold hard clutches
of despair, and yet not be depleted of the possibility (and it could just be a
possibility) that better may yet arrive. This is a kind of hope that is dearly
bought, that does not come lightly but is carved out of a painful vision which
may just be the acknowledgment of all the suffering that life can and does
hold. If anything, the pessimists have taught me this: that with eyes full of
that darkness there can still be this strange shattering openness, like a door
cracked open, for the good to make its entry into life. Since all things are
uncertain, so too is the future, and so there is always the possibility of
change for better as there is for worse.
This can
itself be a moral stance: one that welcomes the good when it is given and urges
it onwards on its journey, but also acknowledges the bad without explaining it
away or overburdening the will of those it crushes in its path. Sometimes we
are not in power to change the world as we would like to, and acknowledging
this can be the greatest effort as well as the greatest consolation, while not
taking away the drive to give our best and hardest labours to the cause.
As
Jonathan Lear has written in his book Radical Hope (2006), one common
phenomenon at times of cultural devastation is that old values lose their
meaning. If they are to survive the collapse of the moral horizon, they need
new meanings, new concepts to breathe life into them. The most difficult thing
of all is to negotiate this change, to start inhabiting new virtues while the
old are still among us. And this, I believe, is one way in which pessimism
might serve us – as a virtue in itself, but also as a way of giving new meaning
to virtues that are changing as part of this changing world. To behold with
open eyes the reality before us requires courage, and not to turn away from it,
forbearance, and yet not to decide that it ends there: this is hope.
Hope –
not that everything will be all right in the end, but that nothing has ever
truly ended; that there is this ‘crack in everything’ of which Leonard Cohen
once sang, in the good as well as the bad, so that neither is ever entirely
shut away from us. This is not the steadfast conviction that things are bound
to get better – not the crude optimism that can no longer be a virtue in a breaking
world, and might prove to be our besetting vice. It may be easier to lend our
efforts under such a banner of assured success, but this ease is a deceptive
one, for while it is possible to be dispirited by passivity or fatalism, it is
possible to be depleted by continued disappointment also. What hopeful
pessimism asks instead is that we strive for change without certainties,
without expecting anything from our efforts other than the knowledge that we
have done what we are called upon to do as moral agents in a time of change.
This may just be the thinnest hope, the bleakest consolation – but it may also
be the very thing that will serve us best in times to come, as a value, and
yes, an exercise of moral fervour: a fragile virtue for a fragile age.
Look on
the dark side. By Mara van der
Lugt. Aeon , April 26, 2022.
“We have
two choices. We can be pessimistic, give up, and help ensure that the worst
will
happen. Or we can be optimistic, grasp the opportunities that surely exist, and
maybe help make the world a better place. Not much of a choice.” Noam Chomsky
In an
age marked by such overwhelming cause for concern for the state of the planet
and the future of mankind as ours, the word pessimism has received a surprising
amount of bad press.
Noam
Chomsky, in the tellingly titled collection Optimism over Despair, puts the
question of optimism and pessimism as something of a forking path: we can
either be optimistic about the possibilities for the future, or we can be
pessimistic, i.e. desperate, i.e. just “give up”. Similarly, and almost
simultaneously, Steven Pinker in his book Enlightenment Now makes his plea for
the belief in progress against what he sees as a widespread current of
“pessimism”, or a belief in cultural decline. Musing from another angle,
Marilynne Robinson strikes out against the “always fashionable” phenomenon of
cultural pessimism, which has the “negative consequence of depressing the level
of aspiration, the sense of the possible”, or even of “encouraging a kind of
somber panic, a collective dream-state in which recourse to terrible remedies
is inspired by delusions of mortal threat.” Even the unborn baby in Ian
McEwan’s novel Nutshell sagely points out that pessimism is no less than an
intellectual weakness, a refusal to see that things have never been better than
in modern-day Western society: “Pessimism is too easy…”
It is
generally a good idea to be at least mildly sceptical when encountering such
sweeping statements, such denunciations of what is obviously or evidently a
widespread fad – and we should be all the more suspicious when no convincing
examples are given of a phenomenon of which we are all supposed to be so
acutely aware. After all: who, these days, calls themselves a pessimist with
any conviction? Where are these black-minded doomsaying pessimist throngs? When
was pessimism ever a thing that was “in vogue”? And who says that pessimism is
the same thing as believing in decline or resigning in despair?
It is in
fact much more difficult to find a self-proclaimed pessimist than a
self-proclaimed optimist, whether in politics, philosophy, science or everyday
life, and the few examples we can find are hardly ever straightforward cases.
Thus John Gray, perhaps the philosopher most notorious for his pessimism, will
not take on the term without qualification: “I am hopefully pessimistic”, he
says on the BBC-programme Desert Island Discs. This caution, this tentative
nature of his self-description, and the very adjective he chooses to moderate
it, are each telling: they reveal what pessimism is often accused of and has to
defend against. But the things we most often associate with pessimism are far
removed from what it really is; they are based on a mixture of misgivings,
prejudices, and concerns that fail to do it justice. For the truth is that
pessimism, or the philosophy properly known as pessimism, was never attractive,
never popular, and never, ever easy. The truth is also that pessimism
represents a much richer, deeper, and more interesting view on life than the
dulled-down version lets us see. Furthermore, not only does this shallow glance
on pessimism dull the truth of pessimism, but it does the same for the contrary
doctrine known as optimism.
***
So, what
are optimism and pessimism? The standard view is that these terms simply refer
to our chosen expectations about the future: an optimist believes things will
get better; a pessimist believes things will get worse. Aside from the fact
that this definition gets pessimism (as well as optimism) wrong in important
ways, the main problem with this representation of both optimism and pessimism
is that it sets the latter up for failure. If the two outlooks are supposed to
tell us what we can expect, and therefore what we can hope for from the future,
then optimism obviously wins, on moral grounds. The intuition is that pessimism
leads to despair, which will in turn lead to resignation: to giving up. These,
again, are Chomsky’s alternatives: we can choose either optimism or despair
(that is: pessimism). If this is indeed the choice before us, then Chomsky is
right, and ethics itself moves against pessimism. We ought not to be pessimists
if to be a pessimist means giving up on our common future, and on our fellow
man.
So much
for the intuition; now for the facts. Do pessimists actually believe their
outlook commits them to resignation? Far from it: in fact, in many cases, the
opposite is true. Joshua Foa Dienstag has devoted an entire book to arguing
that there is a pessimist tradition of political thought, and that pessimism
can be a source of powerful political engagement. How else could we explain the
fact that one of pessimism’s pivotal figures, Albert Camus, was also one of the
most politically committed philosophers in Western thought?
The
problem with the common-sense view of pessimism is that it relies on a mistaken
conception of what pessimism, in its deepest and most significant
manifestations, really is. Far from resting in a belief that things are going
to get worse, pessimism in most cases doesn’t have to do with the future at
all: rather, it is a philosophy that tries to give a place to the darker side
of life, to the reality of evil and pain and suffering in human (as well as
animal) existence. Furthermore, insofar as pessimism is oriented on a view
towards the future, most philosophical pessimists will tell you that to be a
pessimist is not to expect the worst, but rather to expect nothing at all.
Pessimism has to do rather with a limitation of what we can possibly know about
what life has in store for us. It is, therefore, not at all a positive belief
in decline, but rather a negative belief, a refusal to believe that progress is
a given. Thus, to those people who would cleverly say “I’m not a pessimist or
an optimist: I am a realist”, the pessimists could answer that this is just
another way of saying they are a pessimist, in that they suspend judgment on
the question of what is or is not going to happen.
But this
view cast upon the future is only a secondary and derivative part of what philosophical
pessimism is at its most ardent and most interesting: an attempt to paint an
alternative picture of the reality of human life. This, not the caricature we
have become accustomed to, is the beating heart of pessimism. It is also its
original conception.
***
A quick
turning back of history’s pages tells us that the terms optimism and pessimism
first came into being in the early eighteenth century. This happened in the
heat of the philosophical debate on the problem of evil: the question of how an
all-good, all-knowing and all-powerful God could permit the many evils and
sufferings of existence.
Interestingly,
both terms were originally pejorative and oppositional in nature: they were
coined as ways of putting down the opposing philosophy, and this derogatory
nature still clings to them. (To this day, a person can still be discredited by
being called a pessimist, or even, in some contexts, an optimist). Optimism was
the first to be coined, by the Jesuits, to deride Leibniz’s famous system that
we live in “the best of all possible worlds” – and it was the Jesuits too who
coined pessimism as a name for the opposing view. But it was Voltaire’s famous
Candide, or Optimism that ensured the worldwide success of this term, pessimism
following only slowly in its footsteps.
Now if
we look at what both terms meant philosophically, this was to do with a set of
existential questions, such as: Do the goods of existence outweigh its evils?
Is life worth living? Would it have been better for some people, or most
people, or any people, never to have existed? Very roughly sketched, on the one
hand, the “optimists” (such as Leibniz and, most fervently, Alexander Pope),
argued that life is on the whole good, that God’s creation is therefore
justified, and so the evils of existence don’t form an argument against the
goodness, let alone the existence of God. On the other hand, the “pessimists”
(such as Voltaire and David Hume) argued that the optimists failed to give
sufficient weight to the depth of human misery: not only is it the case that
the evils outnumber the goods of life, but the evils carry more weight – they
matter more when we make up the balances. One hour of real suffering, said
philosopher Pierre Bayle, is enough to tip the scales over five or six
comfortable days. Therefore, considering the dreadful potential of human
misery, the terrible extremes to which suffering may reach, existence is a
wager that ought not to have been made. Better no existence, argued the most
dark-minded of these philosophers, than an existence in which suffering could
take such horrific forms. And we all know, they hinted, what the implications
are for Whoever has created us this way.
This, in
a nutshell, is the theoretical question of optimism versus pessimism. However,
behind the theory there stands a profound ethical impulse, one that is equally
active on both sides of the debate.
The
reason the pessimists object so vehemently to the system of optimism (according
to which the parts may suffer but the whole is good) is that it neglects the
reality of suffering, or worse, explains it away. For instance, the optimists
argue that we suffer because we have sinned, or we suffer because pain is useful
to us, or we suffer by our own choice, since we have the power to rise beyond
our suffering. The ethical drive of pessimism is that this is no way to speak
of human experience: that this implies a failure in compassion for our fellow
sufferers, or even that it can serve to make their suffering worse. No
consolation could be less welcome than to be told, in your suffering, that you
suffer pointlessly; that you suffer through your own doing. This, say the
pessimists, is to double suffering with guilt.
On the
other hand, the optimists too are driven by an ethical motivation, their
argument being that pessimists exaggerate human suffering and so it is they who
make suffering worse, by adding to the fact of suffering a reflection upon that
suffering. The pessimists are now accused not only of ingratitude to their
creator, but of moral weakness: here already is the view that there is
something desperate and immoral about pessimism; that it is a failure of the
will.
This
moral concern on either side is, on my view, precisely what saves both
philosophies: it gives them an integrity that they would lack as merely
abstract considerations. It manifests a sense of engagement that takes several
forms throughout the tradition, revealing itself fully in the question of how
to speak sensitively and considerately of human suffering: how to find a
language of compassion and consolation that nevertheless does justice to the
breadth of our experiences. It is also what gives coherence to both traditions,
which are defined precisely by their ethical opposition to each other. Thus
what Voltaire and Rousseau, in their famous clash over the Lisbon earthquake,
are really arguing about is not the abstract philosophical question of whether
we live in the best of all possible worlds, but the proper grounding of
consolation as well as hope. The last word of Voltaire’s Poem on the Lisbon
Disaster is, famously, espérance.
It is,
then, tragic, that throughout the history of philosophy, and up to the current
day, both traditions have failed to recognize this ethical drive in the
opponent, and to take the opposing philosophy truly seriously. Hence the
division that continues today in even the most commonsensical uses of the terms
optimism and pessimism; hence also the caricatures that have resulted on both
sides, and especially those associated with pessimism.
And yet
the person most responsible for pessimism’s bad name is also the philosopher
whose name is most closely associated with pessimism: that arch-pessimist,
Arthur Schopenhauer.
***
The
reason for this is that Schopenhauer, in his argument that life is marked
deeply and principally by suffering, to the extent that suffering is the very
end of life, leads us to the exact conclusion that latter-day pessimists are
most eager to avoid: that we should cease to affirm life, and turn instead to
resignation. In order to achieve “salvation”, on Schopenhauer’s view, we must
radically turn away from this existence, which means turning from our pleasures
as well our pains. We must give up happiness as our ideal, and go beyond
ourselves, our desires, and especially our will, in order to go beyond the
world.
This kind of resignation, haunted as it is by
dark ascetic musings, seems to confirm precisely that intuitive conception of
pessimism as a kind of hopelessness, a philosophy of giving up. It also raises
two questions that strike at the heart of pessimism’s bad reputation. First,
doesn’t this kind of philosophical gloom make for a very potent argument for
suicide? Second, doesn’t it mean we should just stop caring about anything,
including our fellow man? These are the kinds of questions that have resulted
in a bad name for not only Schopenhauer’s particular brand of pessimism, but
for pessimism more generally. And yet Schopenhauer was the first to answer
these questions in ways that should be enough to change our minds.
First of
all: his is not an argument for suicide. Suicide, says Schopenhauer, is not an
answer to the problem posed by existence. An awareness of the reality of
pessimism should place us on a path of philosophical and spiritual
enlightenment, in which we learn to understand the illusory nature of most of
our knowledge and even of our own identities: of that which distinguishes us
from other people. Pessimism is meant to help us find some kind of consolation
in the fact that our suffering is not accidental and is not exceptional, but is
an intrinsic part of our existence in this world. True resignation, for
Schopenhauer, is an attempt to achieve salvation by conquering ourselves, which
can only be done by living in acknowledgment of our human condition, not by
choosing death instead (though what precisely is meant here by “salvation” remains
somewhat mysterious).
It is
yet another misconception clinging to pessimism that its proponents must be
pro-suicide. This is not the case even in that philosopher who famously argued
that suicide is the most important philosophical question, Albert Camus. On the
contrary, the canonical philosophers of pessimism give argument upon argument
against suicide – but unlike most arguments against suicide, which make this
case in moralistic or legalistic or theological terms, the pessimists’
arguments are deeply sensitive to the experience that informs the act, in all
its tragic complexity and profundity. Their arguments distinguish themselves in
that, more often than not, they are formulated from the inside of this
experience, rather than from the outside, looking in. Theirs is an awareness
that suicide tells us something about the darkest corners of existence and
about the depths of human suffering. It is, in their eyes, not at all an action
to be recommended, but an experience to be taken seriously.
As for the
second question, far from making ethics impossible, Schopenhauer wants his
argument to be a foundation for ethics: there is perhaps no philosopher who has
given as much weight to the ethical mechanism of sympathy or compassion as
Arthur Schopenhauer. His central idea is that, by going beyond our individual
wills and pursuing an ethic of personal resignation, we will recognize that
deep down we are all connected by a reality that is greater and stronger than
our individual identities; hence I will recognize your suffering as my
suffering, you will recognize mine as yours, and we will all want to do what we
can to reduce the suffering we see in the (human as well as animal) world. It
thus becomes impossible to turn away from suffering on the grounds that it
isn’t I who suffer: for Schopenhauer, identity and individuality are illusory,
so that a single creature’s suffering properly belongs to all creatures. While
optimism, for Schopenhauer, entrenches us in our personal interests and desires
and makes us insensitive to the suffering of others, pessimism grounds an ethic
of extreme compassion, of suffering-with and feeling-with the other. Far from a
glorification of suffering, it is an extremely compassionate philosophy. True
“goodness of heart”, says Schopenhauer, “identifies all beings with its own
nature.”
***
Of
course, there is still reason to be uncomfortable with almost every aspect of
Schopenhauer’s philosophy of pessimism, and especially with his ethic of
resignation, the giving up of any hope of happiness altogether. Schopenhauer
calls this resignation, but it sounds rather like despair.
Contrary
to this, there is much to be said for an optimist ethic that tells us to look
for the good, the lighter side in all things; one that warns us against
focusing too much on what Schopenhauer calls “the terrible side of life”, lest
we lose heart and hope, lest we forfeit our capacity for goodness and kindness
and for joy itself. Such an ethic would remind us that we must always believe,
even in the darkest of times, that things can get better – which is a view that
Schopenhauer does not allow us, though other pessimists do. This is also what
Chomsky is getting at in his eulogy of optimism over despair. The question is
whether what he is getting at is really optimism, or rather hope.
Could
the two not go together, then? Could there be such a thing as hopeful
pessimism, as John Gray suggests (which to many of us would seem like an
oxymoron) – and could such hopeful pessimism not perform the same tasks as
Chomsky’s optimism, and perform them better? I think it can – and should.
While it
is deeply mistaken to suggest that pessimism is the same as fatalism or giving
up, the concern behind this suggestion is nevertheless a valid one. This is the
concern, voiced most clearly by Chomsky, that if we become too convinced that
things are going to get worse whatever we do, we’ll end up doing nothing at
all. But, as I have argued, this is not at all the point of pessimism, properly
understood. If even that strand of pessimism most oriented towards resignation
(Schopenhauer’s version) retains a profound ethical orientation; if even here
the recognition of suffering in the world is tightly linked to the commitment
to lessening that suffering – what this tells us about pessimism is that this
is a philosophy that sees itself as charged with the highest ethical potential.
Far from dissuading us from ethical or political action, the point of pessimism
is to motivate us.
More
importantly, the fatalistic concern raised by Chomsky goes both ways, and cuts
optimism with the same blade. If it can be said that pessimism risks
demotivation, it could also be said that, if we are too optimistic, too
convinced that things will turn out fine in the end, whatever we do, we’ll
equally end up doing nothing. Why worry ourselves about a complex problem such
as climate change if we already believe everything will sort itself out in the
end; that progress will prevail? How is such an attitude more likely to
motivate us than one that takes seriously the reality of damage, the
reasonableness of due concern?
This is
of course as unfair a representation of optimism as the opposing view is of
pessimism. Again, the point behind both viewpoints and philosophies is their
ethical drive: both are directed towards a common orientation, which is to make
sense of suffering, to offer hope as well as consolation; and, at least to some
extent, to try to improve the human condition insofar as it can be improved.
The difference between both traditions resides in the kinds of moral sources
that are prioritized. To remain with the example of climate change, the
optimists believe we will be best motivated if we draw from humanity’s success
stories, such as new technologies and the vast human potential for change and
innovation, while not focusing too much on the reasons we have for despair. In
contrast to this, the pessimists hold not only that ethics demands we do
justice to the reality of suffering and evils (including the possibility of
impending disaster), but also that this is exactly what will motivate us to
want to make a difference: it is precisely a recognition of the dire state of
affairs in the world that is needed to impel us to action. The disagreement,
then, is ultimately over what is most capable of morally paralysing us:
overemphasizing our capacity or rather our incapacity?
Throughout
the ages, the tension between optimism and pessimism has had to do with the
conflicting demands of their double orientation: towards hope and, at the same
time, towards consolation. On the one hand, this means to do justice to the
reality of human suffering, without which, as especially pessimism recognizes,
consolation is impossible. And, on the other, to offer a perspective that opens
up new possibilities, new perspectives for the future, without which, as
especially optimism recognizes, hope is impossible. This tension rises again
and again in literature as well as the history of philosophy. I will point out
merely two passages, one as subtle in its optimism as the other is in its
pessimism.
The
first passage occurs at the end of Tolstoy’s War and Peace, where Pierre looks
back at his past sufferings and draws from them a lesson that, without
discounting or playing down these hardships, nevertheless manages to place them
in a wider narrative of hope and meaning:
“They say: sufferings are
misfortunes,” said Pierre. “But if at once this minute, I was asked, would I
remain what I was before I was taken prisoner, or go through it all again, I
should say, for God’s sake let me rather be a prisoner and eat horseflesh again.
We imagine that as soon as we are torn out of our habitual path all is over,
but it is only the beginning of something new and good. As long as there is
life, there is happiness. There is a great deal, a great deal before us.”
I
believe there is great wisdom in this. But I also think this is something we
should handle with great caution; something we should not make into too general
a point. It is a wonderful thing when out of deep tragedies or great suffering
comes “something new and good”; when bad experiences teach us new things, help
us to reach beyond ourselves, to grow as persons. Speaking of the value of
life, this is surely one of those things that makes life and living valuable to
us: this possibility of bad things giving entry to the good. But while we
should be deeply grateful when this is the case for us, it is not something we
can count on, nor is it something that is dependent on our will. Not all that
doesn’t kill us makes us stronger. Not all suffering gives way to the new and
good; not all bad experiences help us to grow. Some diminish us, some tragedies
make life stop short in its tracks. Some suffering cuts us off from the
attainment of the “new and good”, and, in Hilary Mantel’s words, makes us
“foreign to ourselves”:
“All of us can change. All of us
can change for the better, at any point. I believe this, but what is certainly
true is that we can be made foreign to ourselves, suddenly, by illness,
accident, misadventure, or hormonal caprice.”
These
words are drawn from Mantel’s memoir, Giving up the Ghost, and they comprise
the second passage I wanted to mention, which seems to stand as a kind of
counterpoint to Tolstoy’s muted optimism: where Pierre counterposed light to
darkness, Mantel counterposes darkness to light. My own pessimism, if it
deserves the name, rises exactly at this point. I believe, with and perhaps
beyond Mantel, that there are those to whom the path of happiness is closed –
truly closed. That there are experiences that can cut us off from ourselves and
from our very capacity for happiness: from the good and from the true. To
recognize this is not to forfeit hope or to give up on such persons, let alone
on ourselves: it is rather to acknowledge that this too is life; this too is
what it means to be alive.
And this
is the great risk, the original sin of any overly optimistic description of
reality or of the human capacity to flourish: the suggestion that this
flourishing is entirely up to us, entirely in our human hands. This very modern
ethic has had its most victorious moment at the heart of the American Dream,
according to which each of us can (and should) achieve our aspirations, if only
we are willing; “you are responsible for your own happiness”. This ethic is
echoed in pop culture as it is in many currents of new age spirituality, some
of which trace back all our good and bad fortunes, even our illnesses, to our
own will and consciousness, thus making each of us starkly responsible for that
which in older days would be referred to fate. Whatever befalls us, so say such
“philosophies”, does so because we have attracted it. This is also an ethic
that fits snugly within the modern Facebook paradigm, where we are supposed
(there is a strong ought here) only to show our happiest face, our sunniest
side – regardless of whether such a side is real or even possible for us. The
pressuring potential of optimism, if wrongly interpreted, reveals itself fully
here.
While
many have surely drawn hope from the belief that our happiness is entirely in
our hands, this is not simply a message of hope. It can become an imperative,
and as soon as it does, it reveals its ugly side, in this overburdening of the
will. This, not incidentally, was precisely what early pessimists such as Bayle
and Voltaire were reacting so strongly against: the idea that we are as
responsible for our suffering as for our happiness. If this gains us hope, it
fails in consolation.
***
A few
months ago I came across a bench by a beach in Scotland that had black balloons
tied to it. The bench itself was dedicated to the memory of a boy who had died
one year before that day. There were flowers on the bench, and beside the
flowers, a bunch of papers, with hundreds of names of persons, followed by
their ages: fifteen, seventeen, twenty-one, thirty-two. On the first page there
was a handwritten and touchingly misspelled note, telling us that this was a
list of people lost to suicide, and suggesting to us these three things:
“ Be kind to people.
Look out for loved
ones.
Its ok to not be ok.”
And this
is what the ethic of pessimism, in its strongest, clearest, cleanest form, most
pivotally represents: that “It’s ok to not be ok.” That to make suffering a
question primarily of our will is merely to increase suffering, by heaping
guilt upon it. That it’s a wonderful thing to live a life rich in wonder, and
meaning, and happiness; and we should be deeply grateful if we are so blessed.
But that our own happiness should not excuse us either from an awareness of the
fragility of life, happiness, and good itself, or from a due consideration and
concern for those less fortunate, less blessed, less beloved, or the truly
miserable among us, who also walk this world.
The
message of pessimism is that this, too, is a part of life, and that it deserves
a place in our language, our shared experience; that we are not justified, that
it is never justified, to close our eyes to that other, darker, “terrible” side
of life. This is also the meaning of compassion in the ethic of pessimism,
which need not at all be in conflict with optimism, but should stand
shoulder-to-shoulder beside it as its necessary complement and companion. As
Schopenhauer wrote, this is how deep down we should greet each other, not as
Madame or Monsieur, but as “fellow sufferer, compagnon de misère.”
***
Noam
Chomsky argues for optimism over despair. We might equally, and more
meaningfully, argue for hope over optimism.
If
optimism risks, on the one hand, an overburdening of the will, and on the
other, an understatement of the reality of true and dire damage done to the
world and to ourselves – could not pessimism serve us better as a moral source?
And where pessimism risks stumbling into resignation – could not hope help us
to mind the gap? If optimism and pessimism both have their faces turned towards
a common goal, could we not find in both the materials by which to travel
forwards?
Why,
then, not a philosophy of hopeful pessimism to guide us into the future?
Pessimism.
By Mara van der Lugt. The Philosopher October 1, 2019.
Dark
Matters: Pessimism and the Problem of Suffering. By Mara van der Lugt
An
intellectual history of the philosophers who grappled with the problem of evil,
and the case for why pessimism still holds moral value for us today.
Princeton University Press
Mara van der Lugt, Lecturer at University of St.Andrews
No comments:
Post a Comment